公 法 评 论

 惟愿公平如大水滚滚,使公义如江河滔滔!
et revelabitur quasi aqua iudicium et iustitia quasi torrens fortis

 


科耶夫:黑格尔导论(节选)

The Dialectic of the Real and the Phenomenological Method in Hegel
Alexandre Kojève (1934)

What is Dialectic, according to Hegel?

We can give a first answer to this question by recalling a passage from the
Encyclopaedia — more exactly, the Introduction to the First Part of the
Encyclopaedia, entitled Logic.

In § 79 (third edition) Hegel says this:

With regard to its form, logic has three aspects (Seiten): (a) the abstract or
understandable (vers?ndige) aspect; (b) the dialectical or Negatively rational (vernü
ntige) aspect, (c) the speculative or positively rational aspect.
This well-known text lends itself to two misunderstandings. On the one hand, one
might believe that Dialectic reduces to the second aspect of "Logic," isolated from
the other two. But in the explanatory Note, Hegel underlines that the three aspects
are in reality inseparable. And we know from elsewhere that the simultaneous
presence of the three aspects in question is what gives "Logic" its dialectical
character in the broad sense. But it must be noted right away that "Logic" is
dialectical (in the broad sense) only because it implies a "negative" or negating
aspect, which is called "dialectical" in the narrow sense. Nevertheless,
dialectical "logic" necessarily implies three complementary and inseparable aspects:
the "abstract" aspect (revealed by Understanding, Verstand); the "negative,"
properly "dialectical," aspect — and the positive" aspect (the last two aspects are
revealed by Reason, Vernunft).

On the other hand, one might suppose that Dialectic is the preserve of logical
thought; or in other words, that this passage is concerned with a philosophical
method, a way of investigation or exposition. Now, in fact, this is not at all the
case. For Hegel's Logic is not a logic in the common sense of the word, nor a
gnoseology, but an ontology or Science of Being, taken as Being. And "the Logic"
(das Logische) of the passage we have cited does not mean logical thought considered
in itself, but Being (Sein) revealed (correctly) in and by thought or speech
(Logos). Therefore, the three "aspects" in question are above all aspects of Being
itself: they are ontological, and not logical or gnoseological, categories; and they
are certainly not simple artifices of method of investigation or exposition. Hegel
takes care, moreover, to underline this in the Note that follows the passage cited.

In this Note, he says the following: (Volume V, page 104, lines 31-33):

These three aspects do not constitute three parts of Logic, but are constituent-
elements (Momente) of every logical-real-entity (Logisch-Reellen), that is, of every
concept or of everything that is true (jedes Wahren) in general.
Everything that is true, the true entity, the True, das Wahre, is a real entity, or
Being itself, as revealed correctly and completely by coherent discourse having a
meaning (Logos). And this is what Hegel also calls Begriff, concept; a term that
means for him (except when, as in the writings of his youth and still occasionally
in the Phenomenology, he says: nur Begriff) not an "abstract notion" detached from
the real entity to which it is related, but "conceptually understood reality." The
True and the Concept are, as Hegel himself says, a Logisch-Reelles, something
logical and real at the same time, a realised concept or a conceived reality.
Now, "logical" thought that is supposed to be true, the concept that is supposed to
be adequate, merely reveal or describe Being as it is or as it exists, without
adding anything to it, without taking anything away from it, without modifying it in
any way whatsoever. The structure of thought, therefore, is determined by the
structure of the Being that it reveals. If, then, "logical" thought has three
aspects, if in other words it is dialectical (in the broad sense), this is only
because Being itself is dialectical (in the broad sense), because of the fact that
it implies a "constituent-element" or an "aspect" that is negative or negating
("dialectical" in the narrow and strong sense of the term). Thought is dialectical
only to the extent that it correctly reveals the dialectic of Being that is and of
the Real that exists.

To be sure, pure and simple Being (Sein) does not have a threefold or dialectical
structure; but the Logical — real, the Concept or the True — i.e., Being revealed
by Speech or Thought — does. Hence one might be inclined to say that Being is
dialectical only to the extent that it is revealed by Thought, that Thought is what
gives Being its dialectical character. But this formulation would be incorrect, or
at least misleading. For in some sense the reverse is true for Hegel: Being can be
revealed by Thought; there is a Thought in Being and of Being, only because Being is
dialectical; i.e., because Being implies a negative or negating constituent element.
The real dialectic of existing Being is, among other things, the revelation of the
Real and of Being by Speech or Thought. And Speech and Thought themselves are
dialectical only because, and to the extent that, they reveal or describe the
dialectic of Being and of the Real.

However that may be, philosophic thought or "scientific" thought in the Hegelian
sense of the word — i.e., rigorously true thought — has the goal of revealing,
through the meaning of a coherent discourse (Logos), Being (Sein) as it is and
exists in the totality of its objective-Reality (Wirklichkeit). The philosophic
or "scientific" Method, therefore, must assure the adequation of Thought to Being,
since Thought must adapt itself to Being and to the Real without modifying them in
any way whatsoever. This is to say that the attitude of the philosopher or
the "scientist" (= the Wise Man) with respect to Being and to the Real is one of
purely passive contemplation, and that philosophic or "scientific" activity reduces
to a pure and simple description of the Real and of Being. The Hegelian method,
therefore, is not at all "dialectical": it is purely contemplative and descriptive,
or better, phenomenological in Husserl's sense of the term. In the Preface and the
Introduction to the Phenomenology, Hegel insists at length on the passive,
contemplative, and descriptive character of the "scientific" method. He underlines
that there is a dialectic of "scientific" thought only because there is a dialectic
of the Being which that thought reveals. As soon as the revealing description is
correct, it can be said that ordo et connexio idearum idem est ac ordo et connexio
rerum; for the order and the connection of the real are, according to Hegel,
dialectical.

Here is what Hegel says, for example, in the Preface to the Phenomenology:

But scientific knowledge (Erkennen) demands, on the contrary, that one give himself
(übergeben) to the life of the object (Gegenstandes) or, to say the same thing in
different words, that one have before oneself and express in speech (auszusprechen)
the inner necessity of this object. By thus plunging (sich vertiefend) into its
object, this knowledge forgets that overview (übersicht) [thought to be possible
from the outside] which is [in reality] only knowledge's (Wissens) own face
reflected back into itself from the content. But having plunged into the matter and
progressing (fortgehend) in the [dialectical] movement of this matter, scientific
knowledge comes back into itself; but not before the filling (Erfüllung) or the
content [of the thought] gathers itself back into itself, simplifies itself to
specific determination (Bestimmtheit), lowers itself to [being] an aspect (Seite)
[merely] of an empirical-existence (Daseins) [the other aspect being thought], and
transforms itself (übergeht) into its superior (h?here) truth [or revealed reality].
By that very process, the simple-or-undivided Whole (Ganze) which has an overview of
itself (sich übersehende) itself emerges from the richness [of the diversity] in
which its reflection [into itself] seemed lost.
"Scientific knowledge" gives itself or abandons itself without reserve, without
preconceived ideas or afterthoughts, to the "life" and the "dialectical movement" of
the Real. Thus, this truly true knowledge has nothing to do with the "Reflection" of
pseudo-philosophy (i.e., pre-Hegelian philosophy) and of pseudo-science (Newtonian
science), which reflects on the Real while placing itself outside of the Real,
without one's being able to say precisely where; Reflection which pretends to give
an "overview" of the Real on the basis of a knowing Subject that calls itself
autonomous or independent of the Object of knowledge; a Subject that, according to
Hegel, is but an artificially isolated aspect of the known or revealed Real.

To be sure, in the end, "scientific knowledge" comes back toward itself and reveals
itself to itself: its final goal is to describe itself in its nature, in its
genesis, and in its development. Just like ordinary philosophic knowledge, it is a
self-knowledge. But it is a complete and adequate self-knowledge — that is, it is
true in the strong sense of the word. And it is true because, even in its return
toward itself, it simply follows passively the dialectical movement of its "content"
which is the "object" — that is, the Real and Being. The Real itself is what
organises itself and makes itself concrete so as to become a determinate "species,"
capable of being revealed by a general notion"; the Real itself reveals itself
through articulate knowledge and thereby becomes a known object that has the knowing
subject as its necessary complement, so that "empirical existence" is divided into
beings that speak and beings that are spoken of. For real Being existing as Nature
is what produces Man who reveals that Nature (and himself) by speaking of it. Real
Being thus transforms itself into "truth" or into reality revealed by speech, and
becomes a "higher" and "higher" truth as its discursive revelation becomes ever more
adequate and complete.

It is by following this "dialectical movement" of the Real that Knowledge is present
at its own birth and contemplates its own evolution. And thus it finally attains its
end, which is the adequate and complete understanding of itself — i.e., of the
progressive revelation of the Real and of Being by Speech — of the Real and Being
which engender, in and by their "dialectical movement," the Speech that reveals
them. And it is thus that a total revelation of real Being or an entirely revealed
Totality (an "undivided Whole") is finally constituted: the coherent whole of Being
realised in the real Universe, completely and perfectly described in the "overview"
given by the one and unique "Science" or the "System" of the Wise Man, finally
emerges from Being which at first was only a natural World formed of separate and
disparate entities, an incoherent "richness' , in which there was no "reflection,))
no discursive knowledge, no articulate self-consciousness.

Taken separately, the Subject and the Object are abstractions that have
neither "objective reality" (Wirklichkeit) nor "empirical existence" (Dasein). What
exists in reality, as soon as there is a Reality of which one speaks — and since we
in fact speak of reality, there can be for us only Reality of which one speaks what
exists in reality, I say, is the Subject that knows the Object, or, what is the same
thing, the Object known by the Subject. This double Reality which is nonetheless one
because it is equally real in each aspect, taken in its whole or as Totality, is
called in Hegel "Spirit" (Geist) or (in the Logic) "absolute Idea." Hegel also
says: "absoluter Begriff" ("absolute Concept"). But the term Begriff can also be
applied to a fragment of total revealed Being, to a "constituent-element" (Moment)
of the Spirit or Idea (in which case the Idea can be defined as the integration of
all the Concepts — that is, of all the particular "ideas"). Taken in this sense,
Begriff signifies a particular real entity or a real aspect of being, revealed by
the meaning of a word — i.e., by a "general notion"; or else, what is the same
thing, Begriff is a "meaning" ("idea") that exists empirically not only in the form
of an actually thought, spoken, or written word, but also as a "thing." If the
(universal or "absolute") "Idea" is the "Truth" or the Reality revealed by speech of
the one and unique totality of what exists, a (particular) "Concept" is the "Truth"
of a particular real entity taken separately, but understood as an integral element
of the Totality. Or else, again, the "Concept" is a "true entity" (das Wahre) —
that is, a real entity named or revealed by the meaning of a word, which meaning
relates it to all other real entities and thus inserts it in the "System" of the
whole Real revealed by the entirety of "scientific" Discourse. Or else, finally,
the "Concept" is the "essential reality" or the essence (Wesen) of a concrete
entity — that is, precisely the reality which corresponds, in that concrete entity,
to the meaning of the word that designates or reveals it.

Like the Spirit or the Idea, each Concept is hence double and single at the same
time; it is both "subjective" and "objective," both real thought of a real entity
and a real entity really thought. The real aspect of the Concept is called "object"
(Gegenstand), "given-Being" (Sein), "entity that exists as a given-Being"
(Seiendes), "In-itself" (Ansich), and so on. The aspect thought is
called "knowledge" (Wissen), "act of knowing" (Erkennen), "knowledge"
(Erkenntniss), "act of thinking" (Denken), and so on; and occasionally "concept"
(Begriff) in the common sense (when Hegel says: nur Begriff). But these two aspects
are inseparable and complementary, and it is of little importance to know which of
the two must be called Wissen or Begriff (in the common sense), and which
Gegenstand. What is of importance is that in the Truth-there is perfect coincidence
of the Begriff and the Gegenstand, and that — in the Truth — Knowledge is purely
passive adequation to essential-Reality. And that is why the true Scientist or
the 'Wise Man must reduce his existence to simple contemplation (reines Zusehen) of
the Real and of Being and of their "dialectical movement." He looks at everything
that is and verbally describes everything that he sees: therefore, he has nothing to
do, for he modifies nothing, — adds nothing, and takes nothing away.

This, at least, is what Hegel says in the Introduction to the Phenomenology:

If by concept we mean knowledge (Wissen), and by the essential reality (Wesen) or
the true-entity (Wahre) we mean entity existing as a given-being (Seiende) or object
(Gegenstand), it follows that verification (Prüfung) consists in seeing (zuzusehen)
if the concept corresponds to the object. But if by concept we mean the essential
reality of the In-itself (An-sich) of the object, and by object, on the other hand,
we understand the object [taken] as object, namely, as it is for another [i.e., for
the knowing Subject], it follows that verification consists in our seeing if the
object corresponds to its concept. It is easily seen that both [expressions signify]
the same thing. But what is essential is to keep [in mind] for the whole study
(Untersuchung) that these two constituent-elements (Momente), [namely] concept and
object, Being for another and Being in itself, are situated within the very
knowledge that we are studying, and that consequently we do not need to bring in
standards (Masss?be) or to apply our [own] intuitions (Einf?lle) and ideas
(Gedanken) during the study. By omitting these latter, we attain [the possibility]
of viewing the thing as it is in and for itself.
Now, any addition (Zutat) [coming] from us becomes superfluous not only in the sense
(nach dieser Seite) that [the] concept and (the] object, the standard and what is to
be verified, are present (vorhanden) in the Consciousness (Bewusstsein) itself
[which we, as philosophers, study in the Phenomenology]; but we are also spared the
effort of comparing the two and of verifying in the strict sense, so that — since
[studied] Consciousness verifies itself — in this respect too, only pure
contemplation (Zusehen) is left for us to do.
When all is said and done, the "method" of the Hegelian Scientist consists in having
no method or way of thinking peculiar to his Science. The naive man, the vulgar
scientist, even the pre-Hegelian philosopher — each in his way opposes himself to
the Real and deforms it by opposing, his own means of action and methods of thought
to it. The Wise Man, on the contrary, is fully and definitively reconciled with
everything that is: he entrusts himself without reserve to Being and opens himself
entirely to the Real without resisting it. His role is that of a perfectly flat and
indefinitely extended mirror: he does not reflect on the Real; it is the Real that
reflects itself on him, is reflected in his consciousness, and is revealed in its
own dialectical structure by the discourse of the Wise who describes it without
deforming it.

If you please, the Hegelian "method" is purely "empirical" or "positivist": Hegel
looks at the Real and describes what he sees, everything that he sees, and nothing
but what he sees. In other words, he has the "experience" (Erfahrung) of dialectical
Being), and the Real, and thus he makes their "movement" pass into his discourse
which describes them.

And that is what Hegel says in the Introduction to the Phenomenology:

This dialectical movement which Consciousness carries out (altsübt) in (an) itself,
both in terms of its knowledge and its object, to the extent that the new. [and]
true object arises (entspringt) out of this movement [and appears] before
Consciousness, is strictly speaking what is called experience (Erfahrung).
To be sure, this experience "strictly speaking" is something quite different from
the experience of vulgar science. The latter is carried out by a Subject who
pretends to be independent of the Object, and it is supposed to reveal the Object
which exists independently of the Subject. Now in actual fact the experience is had
by a man who lives within Nature and is indissolubly bound to it, but is also
opposed to it and wants to transform it: science is born from the desire to
transform the World in relation to Man; its final end is technical application. That
is why scientific knowledge is never absolutely passive, nor purely contemplative
and descriptive. Scientific experience perturbs the Object because of the active
intervention of the Subject, who applies to the Object a method of investigation
that is his own and to which nothing in the Object itself corresponds. What it
reveals, therefore, is neither the Object taken independently of the Subject, nor
the Subject taken independently of the Object, but only the result of the
interaction of the two or, if you that interaction itself. However, scientific
experience and knowledge are concerned with the Object as independent of and
isolated from the Subject. Hence they do not find what they are looking for; they do
not give what they promise, for they do not correctly reveal or describe what the
Real is for them. Generally speaking Truth ( = revealed Reality) is the coincidence
of thought or descriptive knowledge with the concrete real. Now, for vulgar science,
this real is supposed to be independent of the thought which describes it. But in
fact this science never attains this autonomous real, this "thing in itself" of Kant-
Newton, because it incessantly perturbs it. Hence scientific thought does not attain
its truth; there is no scientific truth in the strong and proper sense of the term.
Scientific experience is thus only a pseudo-experience. And it cannot be otherwise,
for vulgar science is in fact concerned not with the concrete real, but with an
abstraction. To the extent that the scientist thinks or knows his object, what
really and concretely exists is the entirety of the Object known by the Subject or
of the Subject knowing the Object. The isolated Object is but an abstraction, and
that is why it has no fixed and stable continuity (Bestehen) and is perpetually
deformed or perturbed. Therefore it cannot serve as a basis for a Truth, which by
definition is universally and eternally valid. And the same goes for the "object" of
vulgar psychology, gnoseology, and philosophy, which is the Subject artificially
isolated from the Object — i.e., yet another abstraction.

Hegelian experience is a different story: it reveals concrete Reality, and reveals
it without modifying or "perturbing" it. That is why, when this experience is
described verbally, it represents a Truth in the strong sense of the term. And that
is why it has no specific method of its own, as experience, thought, or verbal
description, that is not at the same time an "objective" structure of the concrete
Real itself which it reveals by describing it.

The concrete Real (of which we speak) is both Real revealed by a discourse, and
Discourse revealing a real. And the Hegelian experience is related neither to the
Real nor to Discourse taken separately, but to their indissoluble unity. And since
it is itself a revealing Discourse, it is itself an aspect of the concrete Real
which it describes. It therefore brings in nothing from outside, and the thought or
the discourse which is born from it is not a reflection on the Real: the Real itself
is what reflects itself or is reflected in the discourse or as thought. In
particular, if the thought and the discourse of the Hegelian Scientist or the Wise
Man are dialectical, it is only because they faithfully reflect the "dialectical
movement" of the Real of which they are a part and which they experience adequately
by giving themselves to it without any preconceived method.

Hegel's method, then, is not at all dialectical, and Dialectic for him is quite
different from a method of thought or exposition. And we can even say that, in a
certain way, Hegel was the first to abandon Dialectic as a philosophic method. He
was, at least, the first to do so voluntarily and with full knowledge of what he was
doing.

The dialectical method was consciously and systematically used for the first time by
Socrates-Plato. But in fact it is as old as philosophy itself. For the dialectical
method is nothing but the method of dialogue — that is, of discussion.

Everything seems to indicate that Science was born in the form of Myth. A Myth is a
theory — that is, a discursive revelation of the real. Of course, it is supposed to
be in agreement with the given real. But in fact, it always goes beyond its givens,
and once beyond them, it only has to be coherent — i.e., free of internal
contradictions — in order to make a show of truth. The period of Myth is a period
of monologue, and in this period one demonstrates nothing because one "discusses"
nothing, since one is not yet faced with a contrary or simply different opinion. And
that is precisely why there is true or false "myth" or "opinion" (doxa), but
no "science" or "truth" properly so-called.

Then, by chance, the man who has an opinion, or who has created or adopted a myth,
comes up against a different myth or a contrary opinion. This man will first try to
get rid of it: either by plugging up his ears in some way, by an internal or
external 94 censoring"; or by overcoming (in the non-dialectical sense of the term)
the adverse myth or opinion, by putting to death or banishing its propagators, for
example, or by acts of violence that will force the others to say the same thing as
he (even if they do not think the same thing).

But it can happen (and we know that this actually did happen one day, somewhere)
that the man begins to discuss with his adversary. By an act of freedom he can
decide to want to "convince" him, by "refuting" him and by "demonstrating" his own
Point of view. To this end he speaks with his adversary, he engages in a dialogue
with him: he uses a dialectical method. And it is by becoming a dialectician that
the man of myth or opinion becomes a scientist or a philosopher.

In Plato (and probably already in Socrates) all this became conscious. If Plato has
Socrates say that not the trees, but only the men in the city can teach him
something, it is because he understood that, starting from (false or true) myth and
opinion, one can attain science and truth only by way of discussion — that is, by
way of dialogue or dialectic. In fine, according to Socrates-Plato, it is from the
collision of diverse and adverse opinions that the spark of the one and the only
truth is finally struck. A "thesis" is opposed to an "anti-thesis," which, by the
way, the thesis generally provokes. They confront each other, correct one another
mutually — that is, destroy each other — but also combine and finally engender
a "synthetic" truth. But this latter is still just one opinion among many others. It
is a new thesis that will find or arouse a new anti-thesis, in order to associate
itself with it by negating i.e., by modifying it — in a new synthesis, in which it
will be different from what it was at the start. And so on, until one achieves
a "synthesis" that will no longer be the thesis of a discussion or a "thesis" that
can be discussed; an indisputable "truth" that will no longer be a simple "opinion"
or one of the possible opinions; or, speaking objectively, the single One which is
not in opposition to an Other because it is the Whole — the Idea of the ideas, or
the Good.

In philosophy or science born from discussion — that is, in dialectical (or
synthetic) truth which realises the Good in man by verbally revealing the One —
Whole — the intermediate theses, antitheses, and syntheses are aufgehoben, as Hegel
will later say. They are "overcome," in the threefold sense of the German word
Aufheben — that is, "overcome dialectically." In the first place, they are overcome
or annulled with respect to whatever is fragmentary relative, partial, or one-sided
in them — that is, with respect to what makes them false when one of them is taken
not for an opinion, but as the truth. Secondly, they are also preserved or
safeguarded with respect to whatever is essential or universal in them — that is,
with respect to what in each of them reveals one of the manifold aspects of the
total and single reality. Finally, they are sublimated — that is, raised to a
superior level of knowledge and of reality, and therefore of truth, for by
completing one another, the thesis and the antithesis get rid of their one-sided and
limited or, better, "subjective" character, and as synthesis they reveal a more
comprehensive and hence a more comprehensible aspect of the "objective" real.

But if dialectic finally attains the adequation of discursive thought to Reality and
Being, nothing in Reality and Being corresponds to dialectic. The dialectical
movement is a movement of human thought and discourse, but the reality itself which
one thinks and of which one talks is in no way dialectical. Dialectic is but a
method of philosophic research and exposition. And we see, by the way, that the
method is dialectical only because it implies a negative or negating element:
namely, the antithesis which opposes the thesis in a verbal fight and calls for an
effort of demonstration, an effort, moreover, indistinguishable from a refutation.
There is truth properly so-called — that is, scientific or philosophic truth, or
better, dialectical or synthetical truth — only where there has been discussion or
dialogue — that is, antithesis negating a thesis.

In Plato, the dialectical method is still quite close to its historical origins (the
sophistic discussions). In his writings we are dealing with genuine dialogues, in
which the thesis and the antithesis are presented by different persons (Socrates
generally incarnates the antithesis of all theses asserted by his interlocutors or
expressed successively by one of them). And as for the synthesis, it is generally
the auditor who must make it — the auditor who is the philosopher properly so-
called: Plato himself or that disciple who is capable of understanding him. This
auditor finally attains the absolute truth which results from the entirety of the
dialectic or from the coordinated movement of all the dialogues, a truth that
reveals the "total" or "synthetical" Good which is capable of fully and
definitively "satisfying" the one who knows it and who is consequently beyond
discussion or dialectic.'

In Aristotle the dialectical method is less apparent than in Plato. But it continues
to be applied. It becomes the aporetic method: the solution of the problem results
from a discussion (and sometimes from a simple juxtaposition) of all possible
opinions — that is, of all opinions that are coherent and do not contradict
themselves. And the dialectical method was preserved in this "scholastic" form until
our time in both the sciences and philosophy.

But along a parallel line there was something else.

Like all opinion, the Myth arises spontaneously and is accepted (or rejected) in the
same way. Man creates it in and by his ("poetical") imagination, content if he
avoids contradictions when he develops his initial idea or "intuition." But when the
confrontation with a different opinion or myth engenders the desire for a proof,
which cannot as yet be satisfied by a demonstration through discussion, one feels
the need to found one's opinion or the myth that one is proposing (both being
supposed to be unverifiable empirically — i.e., by an appeal to common sense
experience) on something more than simple personal conviction or "subjective
certainty" (Gewissheit) — which is visibly of the same type and weight as the
adversary's. A foundation of superior or "divine" value is sought and found: the
myth is presented as having been "revealed" by a god, who is supposed to be the
guarantee for its truth — that is, for its universal and eternal validity.

just like dialectical truth, this "revealed" mythical truth could not have been
found by an isolated man confronted with Nature. Here too "trees teach man nothing."
But "the men in the city" do not teach him anything either. It is a God who reveals
the truth to him in a "myth." But in contrast to dialectical truth, this mythical
truth is not the result of a discussion or a dialogue: God alone spoke, while man
was content to listen, to understand, and to transcribe (and to do this far from the
city, on the top of a mountain, and so on).

Even after having been a Platonic philosopher, man can still sometimes return to
the "mythological" period. Such was the case of Saint Augustine. But this "return"
is in reality a "synthesis": the myth-revealing God becomes a quasi-Socratic
interlocutor; man engages in dialogue with his God, even if he does not go so far as
to have a discussion with him (Abraham, however, discusses with Jehovah!). But this
divine-human "dialogue" is but a hybrid and transitory form of the dialectical
method. Accordingly, it assumed an infinite variety of forms among the
diverse "Mystics," ranging from true dialogue in which "God" is but a title for the
human interlocutor with whom one discusses, to diverse "revelations" on the tops of
mountains in which the human partner is only a mute auditor, "convinced" beforehand.

In any case, the divine interlocutor is, in fact, fictitious. It all happens in the
soul itself of the "scientist." And that is why Saint Augustine had "dialogues" with
his "soul." And a distant disciple of that Platonic (or Plotinian) Christian,
Descartes, deliberately dropped God and was content to have dialogue and discussion
with himself. Thus Dialectic became "Meditation." It was in the form of Cartesian
meditation that the dialectical method was used by the authors of the great
philosophical "systems" of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries: from Descartes
to Kant-Fichte-Schelling. At first sight, this is a step backwards in relation to
Socrates-Plato-Aristotle. The great modern "Systems" are like so many "Myths" which
are juxtaposed without being discussed, which are created out of nothing by their
authors without coming from an earlier dialogue. But in fact, this is not at all the
case. On the one hand the author himself discusses his "theses" and demonstrates
their veracity by refuting possible objections or "antitheses": thus he applies a
dialectical method. On the other hand, in fact, the Platonic Dialogues preceded
these Systems, which come from them "dialectically" through the intermediary of the
aporetic discussions of Aristotle and the scholastic Aristotelians. And just as in a
Platonic Dialogue, the auditor (who in this case is a historian-philosopher of
philosophy) discovers the absolute truth as the result of the implicit or
tacit "discussion" between the great Systems of history, hence, as the result of
their "dialectic."

Hegel was the first of these auditor-historian-philosophers. In any case, he was the
first to be so consciously. And that is why he was the first who could knowingly
abandon Dialectic conceived as a philosophical method. He is content to observe and
describe the dialectic which was effected throughout history, and he no longer needs
to make a dialectic himself. This dialectic, or the "dialogue" of the Philosophies,
took place before him. He only has to have the "experience" of it and to describe
its synthetical final result in a coherent discourse: the expression of the absolute
truth is nothing but the adequate verbal description of the dialectic which
engendered it. Thus, Hegel's Science is "dialectical" only to the extent that the
Philosophy which prepared it throughout History has been (implicitly or explicitly)
dialectical.

At first sight, this attitude of Hegel is a simple return to Plato. If Plato lets
Parmenides, Protagoras, Socrates, and still others have dialogues, while being
content to record the result of their discussions, Hegel records the result of the
discussion which he organises between Plato and Descartes, Spinoza and Kant, Fichte
and Schelling, and so on. Hence, here again we would seem to be dealing with a
dialectical method in the search for truth or in its exposition, which in no way
affects the Real which that truth reveals. And Hegel does actually say somewhere
that he is only rediscovering the ancient or, rather, Platonic, dialectic. But a
closer examination shows that this is not at all the case, and that when Hegel
speaks of Dialectic, he is talking about something quite different from what is
found in his predecessors.'

One can say, if one pleases, that the eternal light of absolute Hegelian truth, too,
comes from the collision of all the philosophic opinions which preceded it. However,
this ideal dialectic, the dialogue of the Philosophies, took place, according to
Hegel, only because it is a reflection of the real dialectic of Being. And only
because it reflects this real dialectic does it finally achieve, in the person of
Hegel, the truth or the complete and adequate revelation of the Real. Each
philosophy correctly reveals or describes a turning point or a stopping place —
thetical, antithetical, or synthetical — of the real dialectic, of the Bewegung of
existing Being. And that is why each philosophy is "true" in a certain sense. But it
is true only relatively or temporarily: it remains "true" as long as a new
philosophy, also "true," does not come along to demonstrate its "error." However, a
philosophy does not by itself transform itself into another philosophy or engender
that other philosophy in and by an autonomous dialectical movement. The Real
corresponding to a given philosophy itself becomes really other (thetical,
antithetical, or synthetical), and this other Real is what engenders another
adequate philosophy, which, as "true," replaces the first philosophy which has
become "false." Thus, the dialectical movement of the history of philosophy, which
ends in the absolute or definitive truth, is but a reflection, a "superstructure,"
of the dialectical movement of the real history of the Real. And that is why all
philosophy that is "true" is also essentially "false": it is false in so far as it
presents itself not as the reflection or description of a constituent element or a
dialectical "moment" of the real, but as the revelation of the Real in its totality.
Nonetheless, even while being or becoming "false," all philosophy (worthy of the
name) remains "true," for the total Real implies and will always imply the aspect
(or the "moment") which that philosophy revealed. The absolute truth or the Science
of the Wise Man, of Hegel that is, the adequate and complete revelation of the Real
in its Totality — is indeed, therefore, an integral synthesis of all the
philosophies presented throughout history. However, neither these philosophies
through their discussions, nor the historian-philosopher who observes them, effects
the synthesis in question: real History is what does it, at the end of its own
dialectical movement; and Hegel is content to record it without having to do
anything whatsoever, and consequently, without resorting to a specific mode of
operation or a method of his own.

“Weltgeschichte ist Weltgericht" ("World History is a tribunal that judges the
World”). History is what judges men, their actions and their opinions, and lastly
their philosophical opinions as well. To be sure, History is, if you please, a
long "discussion" between men. But this real historical "discussion" is something
quite different from a philosophic dialogue or discussion. The "discussion" is
carried out not with verbal arguments, but with clubs and swords or cannon on the
one hand, and with sickles and hammers or machines on the other. If one wants to
speak of a "dialectical method" used by History, one must make clear that one is
talking about methods of war and of work. This real, or better, active, historical
dialectic is what is reflected in the history of philosophy. And if Hegelian Science
is dialectical or synthetical, it is only because it describes that real dialectic
in its totality, as well as the series of consecutive philosophies which corresponds
to that dialectical reality. Now, by the way, reality is dialectical only because it
implies a negative or negating element: namely, the active negation of the given,
the negation which is at the foundation of every bloody fight and of all so-
called "physical" work.

Hegel does not need a God who would ' reveal the truth to him. And to find the
truth, he does not need to hold dialogues with "the men in the city," or even to
have a "discussion" with himself or to "meditate" a' la Descartes. (Besides, no
purely verbal discussion, no solitary meditation, can lead to the truth, of which
Fighting and Work are the only "criteria.") He can find it all alone, while sitting
tranquilly in the shade of those "trees" which taught Socrates nothing, but which
teach Hegel many things about themselves and about men. But all this is possible
only because there have been cities in which men had discussions against a
background of fighting and work, while they worked and fought for and because of
their opinions (cities, moreover, which were surrounded by these same trees whose
wood was used in their construction). Hegel no longer discusses because he benefits
from the discussion of those who preceded him. And if, having nothing more to do, he
has no method of his own, it is because he profits from all the actions effected
throughout history. His thought simply reflects the Real. But he can do so only
because the Real is dialectical — that is, imbued with the negating action of
fighting and work, which engenders thought and discourse, causes them to move, and
finally realises their perfect coincidence with the Real which they are supposed to
reveal or to describe. In short, Hegel does not need a dialectical method because
the truth which he incarnates is the final result of the real or active dialectic of
universal History, which his thought is content to reproduce through his discourse.

From Socrates-Plato until Hegel, Dialectic was only a philosophical method without a
counterpart in the real. In Hegel there is a real Dialectic, but the philosophical
method is that of a pure and simple description, which is dialectical only in the
sense that it describes a dialectic of reality.

--------------------------------------------------------------------------------


Source: Introduction to the Reading of Hegel, Basic Books, 1969, Chapter One only
reproduced here.
朝圣山之思