公 法 评 论 |
惟愿公平如大水滚滚,使公义如江河滔滔! |
Ronald Dworkin, "Natural Law Revisited"
34 U. FLA. L. REV. 165 (1982)
[Editor's Note: Ronald Dworkin is Professor of Jurisprudence at Oxford as well as a member of the faculty of New York University School of Law. Dworkin's writings have pursued a controversial solution to the problems that have been exposed in the foregoing materials.]
1. What is Naturalism?
Everyone likes categories, and legal philosophers like them very much. So
we spend a good deal of time, not all of it profitably, labeling ourselves
and the theories of law we defend. One label, however, is particularly dreaded:
no one wants to be called a natural lawyer. Natural law insists that what
the law is depends in some way on what the law should be. This seems metaphysical
or at least vaguely religious. In any case it seems plainly wrong. If some
theory of law is shown to be a natural law theory, therefore, people can be
excused if they do not attend to it much further.
In the past several years, I have tried to defend a theory about how judges
should decide cases that some critics (though not all) say is a natural law
theory and should be rejected for that reason. I have of course made the pious
and familiar objection to this charge, that it is better to look at theories
than labels. But since labels are so much a part of our common intellectual
life it is almost as silly to flee as to hurl them. If the crude description
of natural law I just gave is correct, that any theory which makes the content
of law sometimes depend on the correct answer to some moral question is a
natural law theory, then I am guilty of natural law. I am not now interested,
I should add, in whether this crude characterization is historically correct,
or whether it succeeds in distinguishing natural law from positivist theories
of law. My present [164]concern is rather this. Suppose this is natural law.
What in the world is wrong with it?
A. Naturalism
I shall start by giving the picture of adjudication I want to defend a name,
and it is a name which accepts the crude characterization. I shall call this
picture naturalism. According to naturalism, judges should decide hard cases
by interpreting the political structure of their community in the following,
perhaps special way: by trying to find the best justification they can find,
in principles of political morality, for the structure as a whole, from the
most profound constitutional rules and arrangements to the details of, for
example, the private law of tort or contract. Suppose the question arises
for the first time, for example, whether and in what circumstances careless
drivers are liable, not only for physical injuries to those whom they run
down, but also for any emotional damage suffered by relatives of the victim
who are watching. According to naturalism, judges should then ask the following
questions of the history (including the contemporary history) of their political
structure. Does the best possible justification of that history suppose a
principle according to which people who are injured emotionally in this way
have a right to recover damages in court? If so, what, more precisely, is
that principle? Does it entail, for example, that only immediate relatives
of the person physically injured have that right? Or only relatives on the
scene of the accident, who might themselves have suffered physical damage?
Of course a judge who is faced with these questions in an actual case cannot
undertake anything like a full justification of all parts of the constitutional
arrangement, statutory system and judicial precedents that make up his "law."
I had to invent a mythical judge, called Hercules, with superhuman powers
in order even to contemplate what a full justification of the entire system
would be like.(1) Real judges can attempt only what we might call a partial
justification of the law. They can try to justify, under some set of principles,
those parts of the legal background which seem to them immediately relevant,
like, for example, the prior judicial decisions about recovery for various
sorts of damage in automobile accidents. Nevertheless it is useful to describe
this as a partial justification璦s a part of what Hercules himself would do璱n
order to emphasize that, according to this picture, a judge should regard
the law he mines and studies as embedded in a much larger system, so that
it is always relevant for him to expand his investigation by asking whether
the conclusions he reaches are consistent with what he would have discovered
had his study been wider.
It is obvious why this theory of adjudication invites the charge of natural
law. It makes each judge's decision about the burden of past law depend on
his judgment about the best political justification of that law, and this
is of course a matter of political morality. Before I consider whether this
provides a fatal defect in the theory, however, I must try to show how the
theory might work in practice. It may help to look beyond law to other enterprises
in which participants extend a discipline into the future by re-examining
its past. This process is in fact charac-[165]teristic of the general activity
we call interpretation, which has a large place in literary criticism, history,
philosophy and many other activities. Indeed, the picture of adjudication
I have just sketched draws on a sense of what interpretation is like in these
various activities, and I shall try to explicate the picture through an analogy
to literary interpretation.(2) I shall, however, pursue that analogy in a
special context designed to minimize some of the evident differences between
law and literature, and so make the comparison more illuminating.
B. The Chain Novel
Imagine, then, that a group of novelists is engaged for a particular project.
They draw lots to determine the order of play. The lowest number writes the
opening chapter of a novel, which he then sends to the next number who is
given the following assignment. He must add a chapter to that novel, which
he must write so as to make the novel being constructed the best novel in
can be. When he completes his chapter, he then sends the two chapters to the
next novelist, who has the same assignment, and so forth. Now every novelist
but the first has the responsibility of interpreting what has gone before
in the sense of interpretation I described for a naturalist judge. Each novelist
must decide what the characters are "really" like; what motives
in fact guide them; what the point or theme of the developing novel is; how
far some literary device or figure consciously or unconsciously used can be
said to contribute to these, and therefore should be extended, refined, trimmed
or dropped. He must decide all this in order to send the novel further in
one direction rather than another. But all these decisions must be made, in
accordance with the directions given, by asking which decisions make the continuing
novel better as a novel.
Some novels have in fact been written in this way (including the soft-core
pornographic novel NAKED CAME THE STRANGER) though for a debunking purpose,
and certain parlor games, for rainy weekends in English country houses, have
something of the same structure. But in this case the novelists are expected
to take their responsibilities seriously, and to recognize the duty to create,
as far as they can, a single unified novel rather than, for example, a series
of independent short stories with characters bearing the same names. Perhaps
this is an impossible assignment; perhaps the project is doomed to produce,
not simply an impossibly bad novel, but no novel at all, because the best
theory of art requires a single creator, or if more than one, that each have
some control over the whole. (But what about legends and jokes? What about
the Old Testament, or, on some theories, the ILLIAD?) I need not push that
question further, because I am interested only in the fact that the assignment
makes sense, that each of the novelists in the chain can have some sense of
what he or she is asked to do, whatever misgivings each might have about the
value or character of what will then be produced.
The crucial question each must face is this. What is the difference between
continuing the novel in the best possible way, by writing plot and development
that can be seen to flow from what has gone before, and starting a fresh novel
with characters having the same names? Suppose you are a novelist well down
[166]the chain, and are handed several chapters which are, in fact, the first
sections of the Dickens short novel, A CHRISTMAS CAROL. You consider these
two interpretations of the central character: that Scrooge is irredeemably,
inherently evil, and so an example of the degradation of which human nature
is intrinsically capable, or that Scrooge is inherently good, but progressively
corrupted by the false values and perverse demands of high capitalist society.
The interpretation you adopt will obviously make an enormous difference in
the way you continue the story. You aim, in accordance with your instructions,
to make the continuing novel the best novel it can be; but you must nevertheless
choose an interpretation that makes the novel a single work of art. So you
will have to respect the text you have been given, and not choose an interpretation
that you believe the text rules out. The picture that text gives of Scrooge's
early life, for example, might be incompatible with the claim that he is inherently
wicked. In that case you have no choice. If, on the other hand, the text is
equally consistent with both interpretations, then you do have a choice. You
will choose the interpretation that you believe makes the work more significant
or otherwise better, and this will probably (though not inevitably) depend
on whether you think people like Scrooge are in fact, in the real world, born
bad or corrupted by capitalism.
Now consider a more complex case. Suppose the text does not absolutely rule
out either interpretation, but is marginally less consistent with one, which
is, however, the interpretation you would pick if they both fit equally well.
Suppose you believe that the original sin interpretation (as we might call
it) is much the more accurate depiction of human nature. But if you choose
that interpretation you will have to regard certain incidents and attributions
established in the text you were given as "mistakes." You must then
ask yourself which interpretation makes the work of art better on the whole,
recognizing, as you will, that a novel whose plot is inconsistent or otherwise
lacks integrity is thereby flawed. You must ask whether the novel is still
better as a novel, read as a study of original sin, even though it must now
be regarded as containing some "mistakes" in plot, than it would
be with fewer "mistakes" but a less revealing picture of human nature.
You may never have reflected on that question before, but that is no reason
why you may not do so now, and once you make up your mind you will believe
that the correct interpretation of Scrooge's character is the interpretation
that makes the novel better on the whole.
C. The Chain of Law
Naturalism is a theory of adjudication not of the interpretation of novels.
But naturalism supposes that common law adjudication is a chain enterprise
sharing many of the features of the story we invented. According to naturalism,
a judge should decide fresh cases in the spirit of a novelist in the chain
writing a fresh chapter. The judge must make creative decisions, but must
try to make these decisions "going on as before" rather than by
starting in a new direction as if writing on a clean slate. He must read through
(or have some good idea through his legal training and experience) what other
judges in the past have written, not simply to discover what these other judges
have said, or their state of mind when they said it, but to reach an opinion
about what they have collectively done, in the way that each of our novelists
formed an opinion about the collective novel so far written. Of course, the
best interpretation of past judicial decisions is the interpretation that
shows these in the best light, not aesthetically but politically, as coming
as close to the correct ideals of a just legal system as possible. Judges
[167]in the chain of law share with the chain novelists the imperative of
interpretation, but they bring different standards of success璸olitical rather
than aesthetic璽o bear on that enterprise.
The analogy shows, I hope, how far naturalism allows a judge's beliefs about
the personal and political rights people have "naturally"璽hat is,
apart from the law璽o enter his judgments about what the law requires. It does
not instruct him to regard these beliefs as the only test of law. A judge's
background and moral convictions will influence his decisions about what legal
rights people have under the law. But the brute facts of legal history will
nevertheless limit the role these convictions can play in those decisions.
The same distinction we found in literary interpretation, between interpretation
and ideal, holds here as well. An Agatha Christie mystery thriller cannot
be interpreted as a philosophical novel about the meaning of death even by
someone who believes that a successful philosophical novel would be a greater
literary achievement than a successful mystery. It cannot be interpreted that
way because, if it is, too much of the book must be seen as accidental, and
too little as integrated, in plot, style and trope, with its alleged genre
or point. Interpreted that way it becomes a shambles and so a failure rather
than a success at anything at all. In the same way, a judge cannot plausibly
discover, in a long and unbroken string of prior judicial decisions in favor
of the manufacturers of defective products, any principle establishing strong
consumers' rights. For that discovery would not show the history of judicial
practice in a better light; on the contrary it would show it as the history
of cynicism and inconsistency, perhaps of incoherence. A naturalist judge
must show the facts of history in the best light he can, and this means that
he must not show that history as unprincipled chaos.
Of course this responsibility, for judges as well as novelists, may best be
fulfilled by a dramatic reinterpretation that both unifies what has gone before
and gives it new meaning or point. This explains why a naturalist decision,
though it is in this way tied to the past, may yet seem radical. A naturalist
judge might find, in some principle that has not yet been recognized in judicial
argument, a brilliantly unifying account of past decisions that shows them
in a better light than ever before. American legal education celebrates dozens
of such events in our own history. In the most famous single common law decision
in American jurisprudence, for example, Cardozo reinterpreted a variety of
cases to find, in these cases, the principle on which the modern law of negligence
was built.(3)
Nevertheless the constraint, that a judge must continue the past and not invent
a better past, will often have the consequence that a naturalist judge cannot
reach decisions that he would otherwise, given his own political theory, want
to reach. A judge who, as a matter of political conviction, believes in consumers'
rights may nevertheless have to concede that the law of his jurisdiction has
rejected this idea. It is in one way misleading to say, however, that he will
be then forced to make decisions at variance with his political convictions.
The principle [168]that judges should decide consistently with principle,
and that law should be coherent, is part of his convictions, and it is this
principle that makes the decision he otherwise opposes necessary.
D. Interpretation in Practice
In this section I shall try to show how a self-conscious naturalist judge
might construct a working approach to adjudication, and the role his background
moral and political convictions would play in that working approach. When
we imagined you to be a novelist in the chain novel, several pages ago, we
considered how you would continue the first few chapters of A Christmas Carol.
We distinguished two dimensions of a successful interpretation. An interpretation
must "fit" the data it interprets, in order not to show the novel
as sloppy or incoherent, and it must also show that data in its best light,
as serving as well as can be some proper ambition of novels. Just now, in
noticing how a naturalist judge who believed in consumers' rights might nevertheless
have to abandon the claim that consumers' rights are embedded in legal history,
we relied on the same distinction....A naturalist judge would be forced to
reject a politically attractive interpretation, we supposed, simply because
he did not believe it fit the record well enough. If fit is indeed an independent
dimension of success in interpretation, then any judge's working approach
would include some tacit conception of what "fit" is, and of how
well a particular interpretation must fit the record of judicial and other
legal decisions in order to count as acceptable.
This helps us to explain why two naturalist judges might reach different interpretations
of past judicial decisions about accidents, for example. They might hold different
conceptions of "fit" or "best fit," so that, for instance,
one thinks that an interpretation provides an acceptable fit only if it is
supported by the opinions of judges in prior cases, while the other thinks
it is sufficient, to satisfy the dimension of fit, that an interpretation
fit the actual decisions these judges reached even if it finds no echo in
their opinions. This difference might be enough to explain, for example, why
one judge could accept an "economic" interpretation of the accident
cases璽hat the point of negligence law is to reduce the overall social costs
of accidents瓀hile another judge, who also found that interpretation politically
congenial, would feel bound by his beliefs about the requirement of fit to
reject it.
At some point, however, this explanation of differences between two judges'
theories of the same body of law would become strained and artificial. Suppose
Judge X believes, for example, that pedestrians ought to look out for themselves,
and have no business walking in areas in which drivers are known normally
to exceed the legal speed limit. He might rely on this opinion in deciding
that "our law recognizes no general right to recover whenever someone
is injured by a speeding driver while walking on a highway where most drivers
speed." If Judge Y reaches a different judgment about what the law is,
because he believes that pedestrians should be entitled to assume that people
will obey the law even when there is good evidence that they will not, then
it would strain language to explain this difference by saying that these judges
disagree about the way or the degree in which an interpretation of the law
must fit past decisions. We would do better to say that these judges interpret
the law differently, in this instance, because they bring different background
theories of political morality to their interpretations, just as two art critics
might disagree about the correct interpretation of impressionism because they
bring different theories about the value of art to that exercise.
[169]
Any naturalist judge's working approach to interpretation will recognize this
distinction between two "dimensions" of interpretations of the prior
law, and so we might think of such a theory as falling into two parts. One
part refines and develops the idea that an interpretation must fit the data
it interprets. This part takes up positions on questions like the following.
How many decisions (roughly) can an interpretation set aside as mistakes,
and still count as an interpretation of the string of decisions that includes
those "mistakes"? How far is an interpretation better if it is more
consistent with later rather than earlier past decisions? How far and in what
way must a good interpretation fit the opinions judges write as well as the
decisions they make? How far must it take account of popular morality contemporary
with the decisions it offers to interpret? A second part of any judge's tacit
theory of interpretation, however, will be quite independent of these "formal"
issues. It will contain the substantive ideals of political morality on which
he relies in deciding whether any putative interpretation is to be preferred
because it shows legal practice to be better as a matter of substantive justice.
Of course, if any working approach to interpretation has these two parts,
then it must also have principles that combine or adjudicate between them.
This account of the main structure of a working theory of interpretation has
heuristic appeal. It provides judges, and others who interpret the law, with
a model they might use in identifying the approach they have been using, and
self-consciously to inspect and improve that model. A thoughtful judge might
establish for himself, for example, a rough "threshold" of fit which
any interpretation of data must meet in order to be "acceptable"
on the dimension of fit, and then suppose that if more than one interpretation
of some part of the law meets this threshold, the choice among these should
be made, not through further and more precise comparisons between the two
along that dimension, but by choosing the interpretation which is "substantively"
better, that is, which better promotes the political ideals he thinks correct.
Such a judge might say, for example, that since both the foreseeability and
the area-of-physical-risk interpretations rise above the threshold of fit
with the emotional damage cases I mentioned earlier, foreseeability is better
as an interpretation because it better accords with the "natural"
rights of people injured in accidents.
The practical advantages of adopting such a threshold of fit are plain enough.
A working theory need specify that threshold in only a rough and impressionistic
way. If two interpretations both satisfy the threshold, then, as I said, a
judge who uses such a theory need make no further comparisons along that dimension
in order to establish which of them in fact supplies the "better"
fit, and he may therefore avoid many of the difficult and perhaps arbitrary
decisions about better fit that a theory without this feature might require
him to make. But there are nevertheless evident dangers in taking the device
too seriously, as other than a rule-of-thumb practical approach. A judge might
be tricked into thinking that these two dimensions of interpretations are
in some way deeply competitive with one another, that they represent the influence
of two different and sometimes contradictory ambitions of adjudication.
He will then worry about those inevitable cases in which it is unclear whether
some substantively attractive interpretation does indeed meet the threshold
of fit. He will think that in such cases he must define that threshold, not
impressionistically, as calling for a "decent" fit, but precisely,
perhaps everything will then turn on whether that interpretation in fact just
meets or just fails the crucial test. This [170]rigid attitude toward the
heuristic distinction would miss the point that any plausible theory of interpretation,
in law as in literature, will call for some cross influence between the level
of fit at which the threshold is fixed and the substantive issues involved.
If an interpretation of some string of cases is far superior "substantively"
it may be given the benefit of a less stringent test of fit for that reason.
For once again the underlying issue is simply one of comparing two pictures
of the judicial past to see which offers a more attractive picture, from the
standpoint of political morality, overall. The distinction between the dimensions
of fit and substance is a rough distinction in service of that issue. The
idea of a threshold of fit, and therefore a lexical ordering between the two
dimensions, is simply a working hypothesis, valuable so far as the impressionistic
characterization of fit on which it depends is adequate, but which must be
abandoned in favor of a more sophisticated and piecemeal analysis when the
occasion demands.
Of course the moment when more sophisticated analysis becomes necessary, because
the impressionistic distinction of the working theory no longer serves, is
a moment of difficulty calling for fresh political judgments that may be hard
to make. Suppose a judge faces, for the first time, the possibility of overruling
a narrow rule followed for some time in his jurisdiction. Suppose, for example,
that the courts have consistently held, since the issue was first raised,
that lawyers may not be sued in negligence. Our judge believes that this rule
is wrong and unjust, and that it is inconsistent in principle with the general
rule allowing actions in negligence against other professional people like
doctors and accountants. Suppose he can nevertheless find some putative principle,
in which others find [satisfaction] though he does not, which would justify
the distinction the law has drawn. Like the principle, for example, that lawyers
owe obligations to the courts or to abstract justice, [so that] it would be
unfair to impose on them any legal obligation of due care to their clients.
He must ask whether the best interpretation of the past includes that principle
in spite of the fact that he himself would reject it.
Neither answer to this question will seem wholly attractive to him. If he
holds that the law does include this putative principle, then this argument
would present the law, including the past decisions about suits against lawyers,
as coherent; but he would then expose what he would believe to be a flaw in
the substantive law. He would be supposing that the law includes a principle
he believes is wrong, and therefore has no place in a just and wise system.
If he decides that the law does not include the putative principle, on the
other hand, then he can properly regard this entire line of cases about actions
against lawyers as mistakes, and ignore or overrule them; but he then exposes
a flaw in the record of a different sort, namely that past judges have acted
in an unprincipled way, and a demerit in his own decision, that it treats
the lawyer who loses the present case differently from how judges have treated
other lawyers in the past. He must ask which is, in the end, the greater of
these flaws; which way of reading the record shows it, in the last analysis,
in the better and which in the worse light.
It would be absurd to suppose that all the lawyers and judges of any common
law community share some set of convictions from which a single answer to
that question could be deduced. Or even that many lawyers or judges would
have ready at hand some convictions of their own which could supply an answer
without further ado. But it is nevertheless possible for any judge to confront
issues like these in a principled way, and this is what naturalism demands
of him. He [171]must accept that in deciding one way rather than another about
the force of a line of precedents, for example, he is developing a working
theory of legal interpretation in one rather than another direction, and this
must seem to him the right direction as a matter of political principle, not
simply an appealing direction for the moment because he likes the answer it
recommends in the immediate case before him. Of course, there is, in this
counsel, much room for deception, including self-deception. But in most cases
it will be possible for judges to recognize when they have submitted some
issue to the discipline this description requires and also to recognize when
some other judge has not. * * *
2. Is It Delusion?
A. Internal and External Scepticism
I have been describing naturalism as a theory about how judges should decide
cases. It is of course a further question whether American (or any other)
judges actually do decide cases that way. I shall not pursue that further
question now. Instead, I want to consider certain arguments that I expect
will be made against naturalism simply as a recommendation. In fact, many
of the classical objections to "natural law" theories are objections
to such theories as models for, rather than descriptions of, judicial practice.
I shall begin with what might be called the sceptical attack.
I put my description of naturalism in what might be called a subjective mode.
I described the question which, according to naturalism, judges should put
to themselves, and answer from their own convictions. Someone is bound to
object that, although each judge can answer these questions for himself, different
judges will give different answers, and no single answer can be said to be
objectively right. "There are as many different 'best' interpretations
as there are interpreters, he will say, because no one can offer any argument
in favor of one interpretation over another, except that it strikes him as
the best, and it will strike some other interpreter as the worst. No doubt
judges (as well as many other people) would deny this. They think their opinions
can have some objective standing, that they can be either true or false. But
this is delusion merely."
What response can naturalism, as I have described it, make to this sceptical
challenge? We must begin by asking what kind of scepticism is in play. I have
in mind a distinction which, once again, might be easier to state if we return
to a literary analogy. Suppose we are studying Hamlet and the question is
put by some critic whether, before the play begins, Hamlet and Ophelia have
been lovers. This is a question of interpretation, and two critics who disagree
might present arguments trying to show why the play is, all things considered,
more valuable as a work of art on one or the other understanding about Hamlet
and Ophelia. But plainly a third position is possible. Someone might argue
that it makes no difference to the importance or value of the play which of
these assumptions is made about the lovers, because the play's importance
lies in a humanistic vision of life and fate, not in any detail of plot or
character whose reading would be affected by either assumption. This third
position argues that the right answer to this particular question of interpretation
is only that there is no right answer; that there is no "best" interpretation
of the sexual relationship between Hamlet and Ophelia, only "different"
interpretations, because neither interpretation would make the play more or
less valuable as a work of art. This might strike you (it does me) as exactly
the right position to take on this particular issue. It is, in a sense, a
sceptical position, because it denies "truth" both to [172]the proposition
that Hamlet slept with Ophelia, and to the apparently contrary proposition
that he did not. But if this is scepticism, it is what we might call internal
scepticism. It does not challenge the idea that good arguments can in principle
be found for one interpretation of Hamlet rather than another. On the contrary
it relies on an interpretive argument璽hat the value of the play lies in a
dimension that does not intersect the sexual question璱n order to reach its
"sceptical" position on that question.
Contrast the position of someone who says that no one interpretation of any
work of art could ever succeed in showing it to be either really better or
really worse, because there is not and cannot be any such thing as "value"
in art at all. He means that there is something very wrong with the enterprise
of interpretation (at least as I have described it) as a whole, not simply
with particular issues or arguments within it. Of course he may have arguments
for his position, or think he has; but these will not be arguments that, like
the arguments of the internal sceptic, explicitly assume a positive theory
of the value of art in general or of a particular work of art. They will be
a priori, philosophical arguments attempting to show that the very idea of
value in art is a deep mistake, that people who say they find a work of art
"good" or "valuable" are not describing any objective
property, but only expressing their own subjective reaction. This is external
scepticism about art, and about interpretation in art.
B. The Threat of Scepticism
If a lawyer says that no one interpretation of the legal record can be "objectively"
the correct interpretation, he might have external scepticism in mind. He
might mean that if two judges disagree about the "correct" interpretation
of the emotional damages cases, because they hold different theories of what
a just law of negligence would be like, their disagreement is for that reason
alone merely "subjective," and neither side can be "objectively"
right. I cannot consider, in this essay, the various arguments that philosophers
have offered for external scepticism about political morality. The best of
these arguments rely on a general thesis of philosophy that might be called
the "demonstrability hypothesis." This holds that no proposition
can be true unless the means exist, at least in principle, to demonstrate
its truth through arguments [convincing] to everyone who understands the language
and is rational. If the demonstrability hypothesis is correct, then external
scepticism is right about a great many human enterprises and activities; perhaps
about all of them, including the activities we call scientific. I know of
no good reason to accept the demonstrability hypothesis (it is at least an
embarrassment that this hypothesis cannot itself be demonstrated in the sense
it requires) and I am not myself an external sceptic. But rather than pursue
the question of the demonstrability hypothesis, I shall change the subject.
Suppose you are an external sceptic about justice and other aspects of political
morality. What follows about the question of how judges should decide cases?
About whether naturalism is better than other (more conservative or more radical)
theories of adjudication? You might think it follows that you should take
no further interest in these questions at all. If so, I have some sympathy
with your view. After all, you believe, on what you take to be impressive
philosophical grounds, that no way of deciding cases at law can really be
thought to be any better than any other, and that no way of interpreting legal
practice can be preferred to any other on rational grounds. The "correct"
theory of what judges [173]should do is only a matter of what judges feel
like doing, or of what they believe will advance political causes to which
they happen to be drawn. The "correct" interpretation of legal practice
is only a matter of reading legal history so that it appeals to you, or so
that you can use it in your own political interests. If you are convinced
of these externally sceptical propositions, you might well do better to take
up the interesting questions raised by certain sociologists of law璹uestions
about the connection between judges' economic class and the decisions they
are likely to reach, for example. Or to take up the study of strategies for
working your will on judges if you ever come to argue before them, or on other
judges if you ever join the bench yourself. Your external scepticism might
well persuade you to take up these "practical" questions and set
aside the "theoretical" questions you have come to see as meaningless.
But it is worth noticing that philosophers who say they are external sceptics
rarely draw that sort of practical conclusion for themselves. Most of them
seem to take a rather different line, which I do not myself fully understand,
but which can, I think, fairly be represented as follows. External scepticism
is not a position within an enterprise, but about an enterprise. It does not
tell us to stop making the kinds of arguments we are disposed to make and
accept and act on within morality or politics, but only to change our beliefs
about what we are doing when we act this way. Imagine that some chessplayers
thought that chess was an "objective" battle between forces of light
and darkness, so that when black won good had triumphed in some metaphysical
sense. External sceptics about chess would reject this view, and think that
chess was entertainment merely; but they would not thereupon cease playing
chess or play it any differently from their deluded fellow players. So external
sceptics about political morality will still have opinions and make arguments
about justice; they will simply understand, in their philosophical moments,
that when they do this they are not discovering timeless and objective truths.
If you are an external sceptic who takes this attitude, you will have driven
a wedge between your external scepticism and any judgments you might make
about how judges should decide cases, in general, or about what the best justification
is of some part of the law, in particular. You will have your own opinions
about these matters, which you will express in arguments or, if you are an
academic lawyer, in law review articles or, if you are a judge, in your decisions.
You may well come to believe that the best interpretation of the emotional
damages cases shows them to be grounded in the principle of foreseeability,
for example. When you retreat to your philosophical study, you will have a
particular view about the opinions you expressed or exhibited while you were
"playing the game." You will believe that your opinions about the
best justification of the emotional damage cases were "merely" subjective
opinions (whatever that means) with no basis in any "objective"
reality. But this does not itself provide any argument in favor of other opinions
about the best interpretation. In particular, it does not provide any argument
in favor of the internally sceptical opinion that no interpretation of the
accident cases is best.
Of course, your external scepticism leaves you free to take up that internally
sceptical position if you believe you have good internal arguments for it.
Suppose you are trying to decide whether the best interpretation of the emotional
damage cases lies in the principle that people in the area of physical risk
may recover for emotional damage, or the broader principle that anyone whose
emotional dam-[174]age was foreseeable may recover. After the most diligent
search and reflection asking yourself exactly the questions naturalism poses,
you may find that the case for neither of these interpretations seems to you
any stronger than the case for the other. I think this is very unlikely, but
that is beside the present point, which is only that it is possible. You would
be internally sceptical, in this way, about any uniquely "correct"
interpretation of this group of cases; but you would have supplied an affirmative
argument, beginning in your naturalistic theory, for that internally sceptical
conclusion. It would not have mattered whether you were an external sceptic,
who nevertheless "played the game" as a naturalist, or an external
"believer" who thought that naturalism was stitched into the fabric
of the universe. You would have reached the same internally sceptical conclusion,
on these assumed beliefs and facts, in either case.
What is, then, the threat that external scepticism poses to naturalism? It
is potentially very threatening indeed, not only to naturalism, but to all
its rival theories of adjudication as well. It may persuade you to try to
have nothing to do with morality or legal theory at all, though I do not think
you will succeed in giving up these immensely important human activities.
If this very great threat fails (as it seems to have failed for almost all
external sceptics) then no influence remains. For in whatever spirit you do
enter any of these enterprises環owever firmly your fingers may be crossed璽he
full range of positions within the enterprise is open to you on equal terms.
If you end in some internally sceptical position of some sort, this will be
because of the internal power of the arguments that drove you there, not because
of your external sceptical credentials.
We must now consider another possibility. The sceptical attack upon naturalism
may in fact consist, not in the external scepticism I have been discussing,
but in some global form of internal scepticism. I just conceded the possibility
that we might find reason for internal scepticism about the best interpretation
of some particular body of law. Suppose we had reasons to be internally sceptical
about the best interpretation of any and all parts of the law? It is hard
to imagine the plausible arguments that would bring us to that conclusion,
but not hard to imagine how someone with bizarre views might be brought to
it. Suppose one holds that all morality rests on God's will, and had just
decided that there is no God. Or he believes that only spontaneous and unreflective
decisions can have moral value, and that no judicial decision can either be
spontaneous or encourage spontaneity. These would be arguments not rejecting
the idea or sense of morality, as in the case of external scepticism, but
employing what the author takes to be the best conception of morality in service
of a wholesale internally sceptical position. If this position were in fact
the right view to take up about political morality, then it would always be
wrong to suppose that one interpretation of past judicial decisions was better
than another, at least in cases when both passed the threshold test of fit.
Naturalism would therefore be a silly theory to recommend to judges. So the
threat of external scepticism [sic: presumably "internal skepticism"
was intended here], it materializes, is in fact much greater than the threat
of external scepticism. But (as the examples I chose may have suggested) I
cannot think of any plausible arguments for global internal scepticism about
political morality.
Of course, nothing in this short discussion disputes the claim, which is plainly
true, that different judges hold different political moralities, and will
therefore disagree about the best justification of the past. Or the claim,
equally true, that [175]there will be no way for any side in such disagreements
to prove that it is right and its opponents wrong. The demonstrability thesis
(as I said) argues from these undeniable facts to general external scepticism.
But even if we reject that thesis, as I do, the bare fact of disagreement
may be thought to support an independent challenge [to] naturalism, which
does not depend on either external or internal scepticism. For it may be said
that whether or not there is an objectively right answer to the question of
justification, it is unfair that the answer of one judge be accepted as final
when he has no way to prove, as against those who disagree, that his position
is better. This is part of the argument from democracy to which we must now
turn.
3. Is It Undemocratic?
So if we are to reject naturalism, in favor of some other positive theory
of adjudication, this cannot be by virtue of any general appeal to external
scepticism as a philosophical doctrine. We need arguments of substantive political
morality showing why naturalism is unwise or unjust. In the remaining sections
of the essay I shall consider certain arguments, that I have either heard
or invented, to that effect. Of course arguments against naturalism must compare
it, unfavorably, with some other theory, and arguments that might be effective
in the context of one such comparison would be self-defeating in another.
I shall consider, first, the arguments that might be made against naturalism
from the standpoint of what I believe is a more positivist theory of adjudication,
though nothing turns on whether this theory is properly called positivism.
Someone might propose, as an alternative to naturalism, that judges should
decide cases in the following way. First, they should identify the persons
or institutions which are authorized to make law by the social conventions
of their community. Next, they should check the record of history to see whether
any such persons or institutions have laid down a rule of law whose language
unambiguously covers the case at hand. If so, they should decide that case
by applying that rule. If not璱f history shows that no rule has been laid down
deciding the case either way璽hen they should create the best rule for the
future, and apply it retrospectively. The rule they thus create would then
become, for later judges, part of the record endorsed by convention, so that
later judges facing the same issue could then find, in that decision, language
settling the matter for them. We might call this theory of adjudication "conventionalism."
Some people are drawn to conventionalism, over naturalism, because they think
the former is more democratic. It argues that people only have the rights,
in court, that legislators and judges, whom convention recognizes to have
legislative power, have already decided to give them. Naturalism, on the other
hand, assigns judges the power to draw from judicial history rights that no
official institution has ever sanctioned before, and to do so on no stronger
argument than that the past is seen in a better light, according to the convictions
of the judges, if these rights are presupposed. This seems the antithesis
of what democracy requires.
But this argument mistakes the cases in which a conventionalist and a naturalist
are likely to disagree. Conventionalist judges can dispose of cases at the
first stage, by copying the decisions already made by elected officials, only
in those cases in which some statute exactly in point unambiguously dictates
a particular result. Any conscientious naturalist is very likely to make exactly
the same deci-[176]sions in those "simple" cases, so conventionalism
cannot be more democratic because it decides these differently. The two styles
of adjudication will normally recommend different decisions only when some
fresh judicial judgment is required which goes beyond what the legislature
has unarguably said, either because the statute in play is open to different
interpretations, or because no particular statute is in play at all. But in
these "hard" cases the difference between the two theories of adjudication
cannot be that one defers to the legislature's judgment while the other challenges
that judgment. Because, by hypothesis, there is no legislative judgment that
can be treated in either of these ways. Conventionalism argues that the judge
must, in these "hard" cases, choose the rule of decision which best
promotes the good society as he conceives it. It is hardly more democratic
for judges to rely on their own convictions about the best design of the future
than to rely instead on their convictions about the best interpretation of
the past.
So the argument from democracy in favor of conventionalism over naturalism
seems to come to nothing. But we should consider one possible counter-argument.
I have been assuming that conventionalism and naturalism will designate the
same cases as "easy," that is, as cases in which no fresh judgment
is required by the judge. But perhaps a naturalist has more room than a conventionalist
to deny that an apparently "easy" case really is. Consider the following
example. Since naturalism encourages a judge to rely on his own convictions
about which interpretation shows the past in the best light, it permits outrageous
political convictions to generate outrageous judicial decisions. Suppose a
naturalist judge believes that majority will is tyranny. He believes that
our political institutions should be arranged so that statutes are enforced
only when they have been enacted by a two-thirds vote. He acknowledges that
he cannot apply this principle unless it provides an acceptable fit with past
practice, but he sets the threshold of fit low enough, in perfect good faith,
so as to be able conscientiously to claim that all counter-examples (all cases
in which statutes passed by a bare majority have been enforced by the courts)
are "mistakes."
This is no doubt possible. Nothing in the design of naturalism insures that
a judge with silly or mad opinions will not be appointed; but nothing in the
design of conventionalism insures that either; and conventionalism will not
prevent him from reaching preposterous decisions once appointed. A conventionalist
judge needs a concept of convention. He must decide, for example, whether
it is a convention of our society that the Constitution should be followed,
and nothing in the structure of conventionalism can insure that a judge will
in fact reach the correct answer to that question. No theory of adjudication
can guarantee that only sensible decisions will be reached by judges who embrace
that theory. We can protect ourselves from madness or gross stupidity only
by independent procedures governing how judges are to be appointed, how their
decisions may be appealed and reversed, and how they may be removed from office
if this should appear necessary.
But it may now be said that naturalism would encourage anti-democratic decisions
from judges who hold, not mad, but plausible and even attractive political
convictions, and who deploy perfectly sensible theories about how much of
the past an interpretation must fit. For naturalism leaves no doctrine or
practice immune from re-examination. We may use an earlier example as an illustration.
Suppose a firm line of cases has rejected the idea that clients may sue lawyers
who are negligent. Conventionalism is then committed (so it might be said)
to [177]continuing that doctrine until it is reversed by legislation, which
seems the democratic solution. But naturalism encourages judges to put this
line of cases in a wider context, and ask whether the rule refusing recovery
against negligent lawyers would not itself be rejected by the best justification
of the rest of the law, which allows recovery for negligent injury of almost
every other kind. So a naturalist might be led to overrule these cases, which
a conventionalist would leave for the legislature to review.
Indeed there is nothing in the theory of naturalism, as I described it, which
would prevent an intelligent and sensible naturalist from taking the same
line with certain statutes. Suppose an old statute makes blasphemy a crime
and, though it has not been enforced in centuries, it is suddenly revived
by a public prosecutor anxious to make a splash. A naturalist judge might
well develop a theory of obsolescence, even though this had never been recognized
in the jurisdiction before. He might say that the best interpretation of judicial
practice as a whole yields the following qualification to the rule that statutes
are always to be enforced. "Old statutes quite at variance with the spirit
of the present time, which would not be enacted by a present legislature,
and which have not been employed since ancient times, are unavailable as grounds
of criminal prosecution." If prosecutors have not tried to revive old
statutes in the fairly recent past, this qualification would be consistent
with judicial practice, and it might plausibly be thought to show that practice
in a better light, as both more rational and more closely tying what counts
as valid legislation to the will of the people.
So both in the case of precedent and legislation a competent naturalist judge
might find certain cases hard, and amenable to the command of imaginative
reinterpretation, which a conventionalist must concede to be easy even when
the obvious answer is unattractive. So perhaps naturalism would sometimes
produce "novel" decisions by sensible judges that conventionalism
would discourage. But is it right to say that naturalism is for this reason
less "democratic." A minimally competent naturalist judge would
begin his argument by recognizing, indeed, insisting, that our political system
is a democracy; he would continue by arguing that democracy, properly understood,
is best served by a coherent rather than an unprincipled private law of negligence,
and by an institution of legislation that is sensitive rather than obdurate
to changes in popular morality. So the disagreement between naturalism and
conventionalism about which cases are really "easy" is not a disagreement
between those who oppose and those who respect democracy; it is rather the
more familiar disagreement about what democracy really is. When the disagreement
is seen in this light, it is far from apparent that the naturalist has the
worst of the argument. In the next section, I shall argue that naturalism
respects, better than its rivals, a right that has seemed to many people crucial
to the idea of democracy, which is the right each person has to be treated,
by his government, as an equal.
4. Is It Crazy?
A. Instrumentalism
We must turn now to the arguments that might be made against naturalism, not
from the standpoint of conventionalism, but from the different direction of
a more radical theory I shall call instrumentalism. This theory encourages
judges always to look to the future: to try to make the community as good
and wise and [178]just a community as it can be, with no essential regard
to what it has been until now. Of course instrumentalist judges will differ,
among themselves, about the correct model of the good community. Some will
define this in almost exclusively economic terms. They will think that a rich
community is for that reason a good community. Others will take a more utilitarian
line, and emphasize the importance of general happiness over total wealth.
But still others will insist on the importance of personal and political rights,
and will therefore provide, in their account of the good society, that certain
fundamental interests of individuals, like liberty of conscience or a decent
standard of living, be respected at the cost of general wealth or average
happiness.
An instrumentalist judge will see himself or herself as an officer of government
charged with contributing to the good society according to his or her conception
of what that is. Of course a sensible instrumentalist judge will acknowledge
the importance of institutional factors as either an obstacle or opportunity
in this enterprise. He will understand, in particular, that the rules he fashions
must work together with the rules provided by other institutions and other
officials, so that he is constrained by what we might call consistency in
strategy. If the legislature and other judges have laid down rules in the
past that he is powerless to overrule, for example, he must not create rules
of his own which, operating alongside those established rules, would produce
chaos. For that would make the community worse not better off through his
efforts. But instrumentalism denies that judges should be constrained by the
past in any less pragmatic way than that. It denies, in particular, that they
should also seek consistency in principle, by making their decisions conform
to the best interpretation, as the naturalist conceives this, of the past.
Naturalism insists that the past should be allowed to cast a shadow over the
future beyond the pragmatic requirements of strategy. Instrumentalism condemns
this as irrational.
In order to bring out the difference between the two theories, consider this
situation. You think that it would be best, all things considered, if no one
were ever allowed to recover damages for emotional injury. You think this
because you believe that actions for emotional damage involve the risk of
fraud, and force insurance premiums higher than the optimum for economic efficiency.
Of course you think, as part of this view, that no one has what we might call
a moral right that the law provide damages for emotional injuries. If you
thought anyone did have such a right, then you would think that the good society
should recognize that right and enforce it by producing the appropriate legislation
even at the cost of efficiency. But since you think people have no such moral
right you think that society would be better off, on the whole, if it provided
no legal right to such damages.
Now suppose you are an instrumentalist judge faced with a suit by a mother
who suffered emotional injury when she heard, on the telephone, that her son
had been run down by a careless driver. You find, when you search the books,
that the other judges of your jurisdiction have consistently awarded recovery
for emotional damages to relatives who actually saw physical damage to someone
they loved. Of course you think that all these decisions were wrong. You would
be tempted to overrule the whole line of decisions if you could, but suppose
this is beyond your power. The line might include decisions of the highest
court of the state, for example, and you might be sitting in a lower court.
You will nevertheless grasp the opportunity to limit the damage these cases
do to the community's welfare, according to your convictions, by declaring
that only relatives who actu-[179]ally saw the injury may recover for emotional
damage. This will create no practical contradictions, or inconsistency in
strategy.
What objection could there be to this instrumentalist solution to the problem,
assuming as you do, that it conduces to a better state of affairs, on the
whole, than the opposite decision? A naturalist might be led by his naturalism
to the opposite decision, even if he shared your assumptions about the best
state of affairs. He would be unable to find any principled distinction between
seeing and hearing about an accident, and he would be forced to concede that
the best justification of the past recognizes a judicial right to recover
for emotional damage if that damage was reasonably foreseeable. Of course
he might try to show (as the naturalist judge in the example I considered
earlier was able to show about actions in negligence against lawyers) that
allowing recovery for emotional damage was inconsistent with some broader
line of cases. But suppose he could not show this, as indeed he is unlikely
to be able to do. He would then be forced to decide the present case for the
plaintiff mother, therefore compounding the damage to the future. What could
be the possible sense or other merit in that? This is the basis of the instrumentalist
charge: that insofar as naturalism requires different decisions from those
an instrumentalist would reach, naturalism is crazy.
Naturalism seems to assume that in these circumstances it would be for some
reason unfair to decide against her. But why? She has (by hypothesis) no moral
right to a rule allowing her damages. On the contrary, the situation would
be better if no one were ever required to pay damage for her sort of injury.
The fact that our judicial process has made one mistake is no good argument
for making that mistake more general. Of course a naturalist cannot say that
it would be unfair to decide against the mother because most judges in the
past have behaved as naturalists. It would beg the present question to say
that this provides a reason why a judicial decision that offends naturalism
is unfair. For the question at issue is whether it is unfair to reach a decision
which offends the best interpretation of the past. If we want to sustain naturalism
as against instrumentalism, we must argue that the fact that a given principle
figures in the best justification of legal practice as a whole provides a
reason for extending that principle into the future, and we must not rely
on that very claim in making our case for it. But how can we then argue the
case? What can we say to the instrumentalist who claims, reasonably enough,
that two mistakes are worse than one?
B. The Political Order
The naturalist might begin his reply by noticing that the dispute now in play
is wider than simply a dispute about how judges should decide cases. Naturalism
assumes and instrumentalism denies that the members of a community can have
rights and duties against one another, and against the community as such,
just by virtue of the political history of the community. That they can have
rights and duties they would not have if that history had been different.
But this is an idea familiar not only to lawyers but to our general political
rhetoric. Politicians say that America is a democracy, and therefore that
certain things ought and ought not to be done. Or that America respects the
rule of law, and therefore that Congress should not enact certain laws.
We should give a name to the idea behind this rhetoric. Let us say that the
set of political rights people have just by virtue of the political history
of their community constitutes the "political order" of the community.
Naturalism recognizes [180]that communities have political orders, and offers
an account of what a political order is. A community's political order is
provided by the principles assumed in the best interpretation (in the sense
we have been using) of its concrete political structures, practices and decisions.
Naturalism supposes that people have a right to have this order enforced,
in court, on demand. It is not true that every rule of law a legislature or
court adopts is part of the political order, properly understood. The best
interpretation of the order as a whole may show this particular rule inconsistent
with the rest, and so a "mistake" that should be ignored in stating
what the order really is. But if it is indeed part of the genuine political
order, properly understood, that people suffering emotional injury are entitled
to damages against the tortfeasor, then someone who has suffered such damage
is for that reason entitled to a judicial order to that effect.
Of course naturalism is a theory about judicial rights, that is, about the
rights people have to win law suits. It takes no position about how far the
political order furnishes or constrains the rights people have to particular
legislation in their favor, or their rights to revolt or otherwise to establish
a very different political order. If the political order includes a constitution
which, properly interpreted, disables the legislature from changing the present
order in certain ways, then people do have judicial rights, under this order,
that the courts not enforce legislation which contradicts these commands.
But naturalism, as such, leaves the legislature otherwise free to improve
the present order, both in detail and, if appropriate, radically. The idea,
that people have an abstract judicial right to the enforcement of the present
order, imposes a kind of conservatism on politics; but this is a conservatism
imposed on adjudication alone.
Instrumentalism challenges not simply naturalism's conception of a political
order, but the concept of a political order itself. It denies the fact that
political history that has taken a certain form can ever be the ground of
a genuine right or duty at least against a court. This is the upshot of the
instrumentalist's thesis that there are no judicial rights by virtue of the
judicial past. He believes that a judge is never obliged, by the nature of
the past, to work against the best solution for the future. The instrumentalist
argues that the idea that judges are constrained in this way is irrational.
Of course he recognizes each society has a distinctive political past, and
concedes that most people believe their rights and duties are, at least in
some ways, a function of the past. But the instrumentalist holds that this
opinion is silly.
Now what arguments does a naturalist have available in reply? We might begin
by considering one familiar argument a naturalist might be tempted to make,
though only to reject it. Someone might argue that judges should never attempt
to change the political order because this would require them to make judgments
of political morality which ought to be left to the peoples' elected representatives.
So judges should accept the popular idea of a political order, and enforce
that order as history presents it to them, for that reason. This is like the
(bad) argument we supposed a conventionalist might make against naturalism;
in any case it is not an argument a naturalist can make against instrumentalism
because, according to naturalism, a judge must make decisions of political
morality in order to decide what the political order, properly construed,
really is. We labored that point in our description of how a naturalist judge
would go about deciding which interpretation of the past was the best interpretation.
There is, for the naturalist, a crucial distinction between interpreting and
improving the political order of the community, but these are both activities
which engage the judge's moral sense.
[181]
For much the same reason the naturalist cannot use another familiar argument
often made in favor of judicial conservatism. It is sometimes said that judges
do great damage to social efficiency when they surprise litigants by changing
established rules of law. Once again this is an argument that a conventionalist
might be tempted to employ against naturalism. But it is unavailable to naturalism
because nothing insures that a naturalist judge's interpretation of the past
will not prove surprising. A naturalist is charged with discovering and enforcing
the best interpretation of his community's political structure and past decisions,
but the interpretation he believes best may be (as we saw in the example of
Cardozo's decision in McPherson v. Buick) interpretation that has occurred
to no one else. In any case, the argument is a bad argument against instrumentalism
for a different reason. This argument supposes that a novel decision, such
as an instrumentalist might make, will in fact be unwise, pragmatically, for
the future. But if this is really so, then an instrumentalist is ready to
take that into account in deciding which decision will be best for the future.
We noticed that an instrumentalist will look to the past, not as a source
of rights, but strategically, to discover whether his judgment will in fact
have the beneficial effects on the future he supposes. If disregarding some
established line of precedent will actually diminish efficiency, because it
will discourage people from counting on established rules of law in planning
their affairs, then this is exactly the kind of strategic consideration instrumentalism
stands ready to acknowledge.
A naturalist must find his defense of naturalism璷f his idea that the standing
political order is a source of judicial rights璭lsewhere. He must meet the
instrumentalist's challenge directly, by showing why people can have genuine
political rights just by virtue of the actual political history of their community,
and why these rights hold with special force in litigation. Can we find such
an argument for naturalism? We must begin by stipulating a general requirement
of justice in government. Any government must treat its citizens as equals,
as equally entitled to concern and respect. Of course this general requirement
is very abstract. Different people璦nd different societies瓀ill have different
views of what it is to treat people as equals. But we can nevertheless speak
of a general duty of government to treat its citizens this way, and derive
from this two distinct and more concrete responsibilities. The first is the
responsibility, in creating a political order, to respect whatever underlying
moral and political rights citizens may have in the name of genuine equality.
The second is the obligation to extend whatever political order it does create
equally and consistently to everyone.
These obligations are distinct because they can be fulfilled or violated independently.
A society may develop a conception of justice that we, as critics of that
society, reject. In its pursuit of efficiency or other collective goals, it
may violate rights we think people have as individuals, but it may nevertheless
enforce that conception consistently and, in that sense, fairly, allowing
to everyone the resources, opportunities, and protections each is entitled
to have under the theory it has adopted. It may, on the other hand, put in
place an admirable political order; it may adopt a general scheme of principles
and institutions, which we, as critics, approve as exactly what justice requires;
but it may nevertheless fail to enforce that scheme consistently, so that
some people do not have the resources and opportunities the public order requires
them to have.
[182]
Once we recognize both the fact and the independence of these two rights,
we see how it is possible that a government might commit the following special
form of injustice. It might deny to some people a right it has, but need not
have, extended to others. But that is exactly what the instrumentalist judge
I just imagined does in denying the mother her suit for emotional damages.
In one sense the situation that follows his decision is an improvement over
the situation that would have resulted had he decided for the mother. If he
is right in thinking that allowing recovery for emotional damage is not required
by morality, and that it is damaging to the economy, then there will be less
"unnecessary" damage to economic efficiency. But the plaintiff mother
in this case nevertheless has a complaint. Though she has no right to a legal
regime under which people in her position recover damages, she does have a
right that the legal regime in force be consistently applied to her. Otherwise
society fails to give her justice according to its conception of what justice
requires, and that is a failure to treat her with equal concern and respect.
One of her political rights has been violated.
So the naturalist's approach to this case is correct, and the instrumentalist's
wrong, because the former respects and the latter violates the plaintiff's
right to be treated as an equal. This is enough to make out what I am presently
most anxious to show: that instrumentalism is wrong in assuming that the political
order cannot be an independent source of rights. Of course the case I supposed
as an example made it easier to demonstrate that point; it is implausible
to think that a negligent driver has a moral right not to have the law recognize
emotional damages. So the defendant driver seemed to have no proper objection
to a naturalist judge's decision in favor of the mother. We can easily imagine
cases, however, in which even the best interpretation of the community's law
would show that it failed to recognize a substantive right someone ought to
have.
Suppose, for example, that someone sues for damages for invasion of privacy,
but even the most sophisticated interpretation of the law of the community
fails to reveal a principle sustaining any such right. Now the situation reveals
a conflict (as we might put it) between the two rights that follow from the
abstract right to justice. A naturalist judge, who denies the action, will
have upheld the defendant's right to a consistent application of the public
order, but failed to uphold the plaintiff's right to a better public order.
Naturalism insists that the function of courts, at least in a political society
meeting minimum standards of justice, is to address the former rather than
the latter right. No doubt more argument is necessary (which I cannot supply
here) to sustain that choice. Once the two rights are distinguished, however,
and both recognized, that choice is not crazy. Naturalism is not, as the present
objection supposed, irrational.
But what if the condition I just mentioned is not met? What if the best interpretation
of the legal system (or some important part of it) shows it to be wicked?
Suppose that the most sophisticated interpretation of our Constitution, at
the time of the Fugitive Slave Acts, contained no principle in virtue of which
slaves had a right to be free, so that even a naturalist judge would have
had to recognize those unfortunate statutes as perfectly constitutional. An
instrumentalist might well want to say that here, at least, instrumentalism
would provide a better guide to decision, because it would advise the judge
to ignore the constitutional structure, if he could get away with this, and
find some way to thwart the Acts. But naturalism has the virtue, even in cases
like this one, of bringing to the surface an issue of political morality that
cannot be ignored.
[183]
Of course a constitutional structure that permits slavery is deeply defective.
It violates people's first political right: the right to a public order that
treats them as equals. The more difficult issue is this: is there any room,
in this sorry picture, for the slaveholders' second right? Does the slaveholder
whose slaves have escaped have any right, however weak, that the constitutional
system be enforced on his behalf, as it is on behalf of the slaveowner who
has managed to keep his slaves imprisoned at home? If you were a naturalist
judge, you might think that he does. In this case you would have to decide
the Fugitive Slave Cases for the slaveowners even though you despise them
and deplore that constitution, and even though you privately work for a constitutional
amendment or even for the civil war. But you might also come to the opposite
conclusion. You might think that no one can have any right, even a weak right,
to the equal benefit of wicked laws. In that case you would decide against
the slaveowners if you could, because the underlying reason for your concern
with the past, which is people's abstract rights to institutional consistency,
would have exhausted its power. It would not matter if you put your conclusion
in the terminology of older natural law theories, and said that the Fugitive
Slave Acts were not really law. Or if you used the language of modern positivism,
and said that though they were law they were too evil to be enforced. For
the important issue is not what you say but what you do, and though naturalism
does not in itself answer the difficult moral question I posed, it does tell
you what consequences for our decision follow from the answer you give to
that question.
C. The Two Ideals
Perhaps you will allow me a summary of this last part of my argument. Our
political system admits of two ideals; it is imperfect in two ways. It stands
in the shadow of an external ideal, which is the ideal of a perfectly just
and effective system. This is the challenge it offers to legislation, and,
beyond that, to the political will and sense of justice of the community which
has the standing power to make it better, closer to the external ideal of
what a political system should be. But unless it is a very bad political system
it stands also in the shadow of a different, internal ideal, which is the
ideal of itself made pure. This is the challenge it offers to adjudication:
the challenge of making the standards that govern our collective lives articulate,
coherent and effective. Naturalism insists on the difference between the two
ideals, and makes that difference the nerve of the rule of law.
People will disagree about what the internal ideal of our order is like, perhaps
just as much as they disagree about what external ideal our order should pursue.
Indeed they will disagree about the former precisely because they disagree
about the latter. So no one will have any guarantee that, if he should come
to court, those who judge him according to naturalism will reach the result
that he himself thought was the best interpretation of our order when he acted.
That is inevitable in any community which recognizes what is plainly true:
that people have rights beyond the rights conventionalism recognizes, that
is, that they have rights beyond the strict and narrow limits within which
everyone agrees what these rights are. But naturalism at least takes the actual
political order, properly interpreted, as the common standard, so that citizens
are encouraged to put to themselves the same questions that officials who
adjudicate their disputes will ask in judging them. No doubt this practice
will cause surprise and disappointment, even despair. No doubt it will produce
injustice. Its virtue is that it seems less vulnerable, in all these respects,
than available alternatives for bringing the rule of principle to an imperfect
world.
[184]
We can, as a community, strive towards these two ideals at the same time,
though through different institutions and practice. We embrace the two ideals
as an agenda for sustained and continuing debate. We have no hope璦nd indeed
no wish璽hat the debate will end. We understand that the decision of political
officials must be accepted, from time to time. But we insist that this is
only because someone's decisions must be accepted and not because these decisions
come guaranteed for accuracy. We know that the quality of the debate is itself,
quite apart from any agreement it might produce, something that makes ourselves
and our community better. This is the image we should have of politics and
of our lives in politics. Our courts play a distinct sovereign and indispensable
role in this image. They are the forum of the second ideal.
Notes
1. At an earlier time, Professor Fuller had suggested a less literary analogy
than the chain novel of Professor Dworkin. Fuller supposed:
An inventor of useful household devices dies leaving the pencil sketch of
an invention on which he was working at the time of his death. On his deathbed
he requests his son to continue work on the invention, though he dies without
having had a chance to tell the son what purpose the invention was to serve
or anything about his own plans for completing it. In carrying out his father's
wish the son's first step would be to decide what the purpose of the projected
invention was, what defect or insufficiency of existing devices it was intended
to remedy. He would then try to grasp the underlying principle of the projected
invention, the "true reason of the remedy"....With these problems
solved he would then proceed to work out what was essential to complete the
design for the projected device.
L. FULLER, THE MORALITY OF LAW 84-85 (rev. ed. 1969). Also, Fuller argued
that his desideratum about avoiding logically contradictory rules can be extended
to the need to avoid rules that are inconsistent in underlying principle.
Is there any significant difference between Fuller's and Dworkin's approach?
Which do you think is better?
2. Notice that Dworkin's theory goes beyond an account of pure common-law
decision making; he would apply the same methodology in cases involving the
interpretation of statutes. What do you suppose Dworkin would think about
the decision in Riggs v. Palmer? See RONALD DWORKIN, LAW'S EMPIRE 15-20 &
passim (1986) (discussing Riggs in depth). The methodology can also be applied
in the context of constitutional issues: How, for example, might it work in
the context of the fugitive slave controversy sampled in Prigg? See Ronald
Dworkin, The Law of the Slave-Catchers (reviewing R. COVER, JUSTICE ACCUSED
(1975)), TIMES LITERARY SUPPLEMENT, Dec. 5, 1975, at 1437 (arguing that the
fugitive slave laws could have been considered unconstitutional "mistakes"
when viewed in terms of the interpretation of the constitution as a whole).
This page was last modified on February 18, 1999.
The Justice and the Legal System website is administered by L. Daniel Liutikas.
Entire contents ?1998-99. All rights reserved