公 法 评 论 http://www.gongfa.com/
The
Common Law Character of English Charters:
Spontaneous
Order in the Constitutions of Clarendon (1164)
Robert
F. Mulligan
Western
Carolina University College of Business
and the
State University of New York at Binghamton
Medieval
English kings commemorated their coronation with charters enumerating rights,
privileges, and legal principles. Coronation
charters were transmitted to each county sheriff or reeve, and maintained in monasteries or other
secure places. In taking the oath
of office, the king swore to govern, respect the laws and customs of the realm,
and defend the Church. A
coronation charter embodied an explicit execution of the oath, asserting the
laws and customs the king was to protect.
Mention of rights in a charter was not always sufficient to guarantee
their exercise, but was as often as not.
As
legal practice evolved, this evolution was embodied in successive
charters. Kings also issued
charters to address political exigencies.
Although medieval charters are precursors of modern parliamentary
legislation, they were more often declarative of existing laws and customs,
than originative of positive law. Charters
occasionally introduced legal innovation, but always in the context of the
common law. Positive legislation
in medieval English charters is generally conservative, often aiming at
improving the implementation of common law. In contrast, charters were often aggressive in restoring
ancient liberties and customs.
The
highly conservative nature of legislation-by-charter is seen in the fact that
many charter articles reversed practical innovations and aimed at restoring
earlier states of affairs. In
particular, Henry II's (1154-1189) charters are filled with references to the
customs of the time of his grandfather Henry I (1100-1135), which are often
formally restored. The intervening
reign of Stephen (1135-1154) was a time of civil war and lawlessness, and Henry
II's primary mission was the restoration of law and order. Henry II's charters were probably the
most effective instrument to effect that end.
Charters
were ratified by great councils of the kingdom, which included the king, and
representatives of the nobility and clergy. Because great councils often convened without producing
charters, this paper refers to a great council which produced a charter as a
charter assembly.
Charters were not formally drafted by
the king, but by ad hoc councils of justicars, clergy, and nobles who deliberated
draft articles, perhaps influencing revision, perhaps not. Henderson (1896) ascribes authorship of
the Constitutions of Clarendon to two justicars. Many signatories only participated as witnesses and
guarantors. The king essentially
dictated the content by directing which matters ought to be examined by a great
council - he set the agenda.
This paper argues that royal charters
played a common-law role in medieval English society, and thus contributed to
social and economic progress, facilitating entrepreneurial discovery. Although
charters are not generally considered part of the common law, because they are
not judge-given, charter assemblies were, in fact, ad hoc grand juries. Although the crown often convened great
councils as charter assemblies with specific policy goals in mind, English
kings always gave explicit and formal acknowledgement of the superior authority
of preexisting custom, law, and tradition. Royal charters are one of the most visible legacies of a
system of spontaneously evolving rules which governed society. In respecting common-law tradition,
kings promoted economic and other forms of political liberty by confirming and
maintaining abstract rules binding on all member of society, including
themselves.
The remainder of this paper is organized
as follows. Section 1 reviews the
history of the concept of spontaneous order in social organization. Section 2 offers a brief discussion of
the contribution to this intellectual tradition made by Mario Rizzo
(1985). Section 3 demonstrates how
the Constitutions of Clarendon, the most important medieval document providing
a foundation for the separation of church and state in England, illustrate the
spontaneous emergence of a tradition-based legal order. Section 4 elucidates the concept of
abstract rules embodied in common law and discusses the extent they allow
entrepreneurs to overcome certain knowledge problems. Section 5 presents some concluding remarks.
1. Spontaneous Order in Law: Plato,
Menger, and Hayek
The
idea of spontaneous order in law is at least as old as Plato, who mentions in
The Laws (IV, 4) that no human being can arbitrarily create laws; they evolve
over time as human circumstances evolve for the laws to address, and individual
human legislators add minor practical innovations. Montesquieu (Spirit of the Laws, I, 1) adopts a similar
position; though he recognizes positive legislation also helps shape state
institutions, these institutions derive their fundamental character and basic
legitimacy from social custom and evolution. Burke expresses the emergence of spontaneous order:
"From
magna charta to the declaration of right, it has been the uniform policy of our
constitution to claim and assert our liberties as an entailed inheritance
derived to us from our forefathers, and to be transmitted to our
posterity." (1792, III, p. 58.)
Ancient
and medieval law was thought to embody concepts of right and wrong: "What
is right is not derived from the rule but the rule derives from our knowledge
of what is right." (Julius Paulus, Digests, 50.17.1) Hayek relates how early law-giving
consisted only of the practice of recording and disseminating laws conceived of
as being unalterably given. (Hayek 1973 [hereafter LLL I], p. 81) "A 'legislator' might endeavour to
purge the law of supposed corruptions, but it was not thought that he could
make new law… changes which did occur were not the result of intention or
design of a law-maker…. The idea that law might be created by men is alien to
the thinking of early people." (LLL I, p. 81) The Code of Justinian was based on classical Roman civil
law, which was predominantly the product of law-finding by jurists and includes
very little positive legislation.
The Code of Justinian was wrongly
supposed to have been imposed by the ruler and expressive of his will.
Until
the rediscovery of Aristotle's Politics in the thirteenth century and the
reception of Justinian's code in the fifteenth, however, Western Europe passed
through another epoch of nearly a thousand years when law was again regarded as
something given independently of human will, something to be discovered, not
made, and when the conception that law could be deliberately made or altered
seemed almost sacrilegious. (LLL I, p. 83)
When
new law was made, it was in the belief that what was being made was good old
law, not expressly handed down, but tacitly existent. The law was not felt to have been made, but
"discovered." "There
is, in the Middle Ages, no such thing as the 'first application of a legal
rule.' Law is old; new law is a
contradiction in terms; for either new law is derived explicitly or implicitly
from the old, or it conflicts with the old, in which case it is not lawful…. The
old law is the true law, and the true law is the old law…. all legislation and
legal reform is conceived of as the restoration of the good old law which has
been violated." (Kern 1939, p. 151)
Menger
(1883, pp. 223-234) addresses the emergence of a spontaneous social order,
arguing against the prevailing view of the German historical school. Menger's view is that law originated
with implicit rules of action which promoted security in early societies, and
which came to be acknowledged as binding on individual conduct. Later generations, sufficiently removed
from the factual origin of the law, might posit the inspiration of a higher
divine wisdom. Menger recognizes a
second source of the law in authority, which can impose rules on the governed
without consent, obtaining submission from fear. Menger describes this kind of positive legislation as
statute, not law (p. 229). Interestingly,
Menger also suggests positive legislation becomes more necessary as
civilization progresses and social organization becomes more
sophisticated. He insists the true
aim of jurisprudence is not the absolute avoidance of positive legislation, but
the construction positive legislation informed by and which embodies whatever
is best in the common law (p. 234).
As will be seen below, what positive legislation is contained in the
medieval charters, satisfies this requirement and was clearly intended for that
purpose.
Hayek
notes that England was the only country that succeeded in preserving the
medieval common-law tradition of "liberties" in its modern conception
of liberty under the law. This was
partly because England avoided a massive influx of later Roman law in the form
of the Code of Justinian and the accompanying misconception of law as the
arbitrary dictate of an omnipotent ruler.
A further circumstance Hayek cites is that English common-law jurists
developed something similar to the natural law doctrine of the late Spanish
schoolmen, who used "natural" in a technical sense to describe that
which was not artificial, "what had never been invented or deliberately
designed but had evolved in response to the necessity of the situation." (LLL
I, p. 84) Hayek notes natural law
later came to mean law designed according to natural reason, often applying to
positive law.
The political freedom of the United
Kingdom in the eighteenth century was clearly not a product of a designed
separation of powers between the legislature and the executive, as Montesquieu
believed. To the extent this
separation of powers was real, in England it was the product of evolution, not
design. Hayek claims the real
source of British freedom was the fact that common law existed independent of
the will of any court, jurist, or legislator; this law was binding on and at
the same time developed by the courts independent of the legislature;
parliament rarely interfered with the common law and did so mainly to address
doubtful points when they arose in a given body of law. Hayek says "a sort of separation
of powers had grown up in England, not because the 'legislature' alone made
law, but because it did not." (LLL I, p. 85)
Hayek discusses the origin of
positive-law-making legislatures in the modern sense. If the following passage about the nature and origin of
legislation is accepted, it becomes clear that it perfectly describes the the
twelfth-century charter assemblies:
"But
if the laying down of such rules for the organizations of government was long
regarded as the 'prerogative' of its head, the need for an approval of, or a
consent to, his measure by representative or constituted bodies would often
arise precisely because the ruler was himself supposed to be bound by the
established law. And when, as in
levying contributions in money or services for the purposes of government, he
had to use coercion in a form not clearly prescribed by the established rules,
he would have to assure himself of the support at least of his more powerful
subjects. It would then often be
difficult to decide whether they were merely called in to testify that this or
that was established law or to approve of a particular imposition or measure
thought necessary for a particular end." (LLL I, p. 90)
It is
clear the charter assemblies acted as witnesses at least. They may sometimes have also acted in a
consenting or approving capacity.
2. Rizzo's Synthesis
Rizzo
(1985, p. 882) frames the thesis that "the pure common law process
produces abstract rules that do not impose a particular hierarchy of ends on
society, but simply facilitate the attainment of various individual ends." In contrast to the prevailing view that
jurisprudence must balance competing social interests in the formulation of
society's contract, property, and tort rules, Rizzo notes common law can be
policy neutral through the avoidance of a specific hierarchy of values. This is accomplished through the
provision of abstract rules that enhance the possibilities of an order in which
individuals are free to pursue and attain their own goals. Individuals choose their own
values freely and society does not impose any explicit value hierarchy on individuals.
The
common law is itself a spontaneous order that is not the result of conscious
direction by legislative authorities.
It is a body of legal principles, i.e., formal rules, which evolved
incrementally through the participation, and occasional minor innovation, of
many individual jurists, over time.
Law arising from custom and precedent
"will consist of purpose-independent rules which govern the conduct of
individuals towards each other, are intended to apply to an unknown number of
further instances, and … enable an order of actions to form itself wherein the
individuals can make feasible plans." (LLL I, pp. 85-86) Common law generally possesses a more
abstract character than positive legislation: the common law "does not
consist of particular cases, but of general principles, which are illustrated
and explained by those principles." (LLL I, p. 86) Common law precedents allow for the
derivation of rules of universal significance applicable to new cases.
Positive
legislation is necessary in some cases.
"The spontaneous process of growth may lead into an impasse from
which it cannot extricate itself by its own forces or which it will at least
not correct quickly enough…. Case-law is in some respects a sort of one-way
street: when it has already moved a considerable distance in one direction, it
often cannot retrace its steps when some implications of earlier decisions are
seen to be clearly undesirable." (LLL I, p. 88)
At the
time of the Constitutions of Clarendon (1164) a body of case law had developed
during the preceding reign of Stephen, establishing a significantly broader
range of jurisdiction for the canon law courts. It would have been extremely tedious to limit future
expansion of canon-law jurisdiction, much less restore the original balance
between canon and civil authorities.
The whole outcome of the enterprise would have been uncertain, and it is
unclear whether or how the king could have affected change in canon law through
civil case law decisions.
"It
is not only difficult but undesirable for judicial decisions to reverse a
development, which has already taken place and is then seen to have undesirable
consequences or to be downright wrong.
The judge is not performing his function if he disappoints reasonable
expectations created by earlier decisions. Although the judge can develop the law he cannot
really alter it, or can do so at most only very gradually where a rule has
become firmly established….the new rule should become known before it is
enforced…. Where a real change in the law is required, the new law can properly
fulfil the proper function of all law, namely that of guiding expectations,
only if it becomes known before it is applied." (LLL I, pp. 85-86) It is clear that English charters often
acted to correct or restore the common law.
"When some basic principles of the
law have been accepted for a long time, they will govern the whole system of
law, its general spirit as well as every single rule and application within
it. At such times it will possess
great inherent stability." (LLL I, p. 66) Stable rules provide one of the necessary conditions
for entrepreneurial activity and economic planning. A contrasting situation had developed during the civil
disturbances of the reign of Stephen.
"The situation is entirely different, however, when a general
philosophy of law which is not in accord with the greater part of the existing
law has recently gained ascendancy.
The same lawyers…become a revolutionary force, as effective in
transforming the law down to every detail as they were before in preserving
it." (LLL I, p. 66)
"Groups which happen to have
adopted rules conducive to a more effective order of actions will tend to
prevail over other groups with a less effective order. The rules which spread will be those
governing the practice or customs existing in different groups which make some
groups stronger than others." (LLL I, p. 99; cf. Pollock, 1890, p. 41,
"the historical method is nothing else than the doctrine of evolution
applied to human societies and institutions.") "The task of rules of just conduct can thus only be to
tell people which expectations they can count on and which not." (LLL I,
p. 102) This is what Hayek and
Rizzo refer to as the macro function of rules - better rules make some
societies better suited for survival than others. Often these rules which confer survivability are consciously
imitated.
Hayek and Rizzo also identify a micro
function of rules - rules allow us to predict the conduct of other agents and
minimize the range of uncertainty individual agents have to address in making
their decisions. Kirzner (1990b)
contrasts the planned process of production of goods and services with the
spontaneous act of perceptive discovery.
To consider an example, some treason
statutes are very ancient, but English history is filled with new and bizarre
innovations in treason legislation.
All are positive. The U.S.
Constitution makes treason consist of making war on the United States or giving
aid and comfort to their enemies, and specifies no one can be convicted of this
crime except for committing an overt act and on the testimony of at least two
witnesses. Various English treason
laws made imagining the sovereign's death, deposition, or damnation a capital
offense. It seems more likely that
positive legislation, not as strongly bound by precedent and tradition, can
proceed to such extremes, than common law.
2.1
Moral Authority and Legitimacy
Hayek (1960, p. 201) notes the rule of
law cannot prevail in a democracy unless it forms part of the moral tradition
of the community.
Coronation
charters often formally granted liberties and privileges to the chief nobles
and clergy. Obtaining support of
the English baronage was essential for the king to hold the crown
securely. William I, Henry I,
Stephen, and Henry II did not inherit the throne through any regular legal
process. Granting rights by
charter was one way to assure support and it would be interesting to analyze
these charters from a public choice theory of government perspective. Only later were the common people
included in the grant of rights-by-charter.
The
king's conflict with the Church can be equally well viewed as an attempt to
defend his own rights and revenues from encroachment, as an effort to protect
the common people from expansion of the Church's rights and power. Furthermore, in the English conception,
the sovereign was subject to the laws and customs of the realm, not above them.
"The
most frequent cause of uncertainty is probably that the order of rank of the
different rules belonging to a system is only vaguely determined." (Hayek
1976 [hereafter LLL II], p. 24.) As
will be seen below in the very text of the Constitutions of Clarendon, any
assertion of customary rights can never be exhaustive, and in being selective,
necessarily addresses this objection of Hayek's. Issue and reissue of charters enumerating traditional rights
served to mitigate, even if it could never remove entirely, uncertainty and
vagueness faced by economic agents.
Charter
articles occasionally introduced positive legislation in the sense that they
sometimes specified procedures for disposing of legal issues in accordance with
established law and custom. Sometimes
they merely confirmed or reestablished traditional procedural rights and practices.
The
Constitutions explicitly state that they are not an exhaustive or final
assertion of the laws and customs: "There are, moreover, many other and
great customs and dignities of the holy mother church, and of the lord king,
and of the barons of the kingdom, which are not contained in this writ. And may
they be preserved to the holy church, and to the lord king, and to his heirs,
and to the barons of the kingdom, and may they be inviolably observed for
ever."
Although
there was some effort to separate civil and church courts in Saxon times, the
division was not fully implemented until after the conquest and can be
considered a Norman innovation. The
jurisdictions, once separated, began to evolve independent common law. Hume (1778, I, p. 185) records that
Edgar (959-975) passed a law attempting to separate ecclesiastic and civil
jurisdictions, but even after the conquest, William the Conqueror still had to
pass a special law to implement the division. Henry I reunited the civil and church courts in the
coronation charter, by promising to restore the Code of Edward the Confessor,
but this solemn promise remained without effect.
2.2
Nature of the Spontaneous Order
In
issuing a charter, the king was not primarily promulgating positive law. He could be understood to be requesting
the charter assembly or great council of the kingdom to attempt one of three
tasks, or any combination. The
council could, a. testify with respect to their consensus understanding of the
established and true laws of the realm, b. research, consult, and formulate
such an understanding, prior to advising the king, or c. provide assent or
advice on the king's own proposed interpretation and implementation of the
established laws and customs, or that of his closest advisors.
Charter
assemblies provided positive legislation only incidentally, and almost entirely
in setting forth new practices for the implementation of old and venerable
laws, rights, and privileges. Clearly
one reason for the relative absence of positive legislation from the charters
is the fact that kings could issue positive law on their own authority without
the cumbersome and expensive procedure of convening a great council.
"The
common law is a dynamic order that allows for and even promotes change. It is also an abstract order that is
unbound by the specific value hierarchies or compromises of its judges. The purpose of the law is to promote
'that abstract order of the whole which does not aim at the achievement of
known particular results but is preserved as a means for assisting in the
pursuit of a great variety of individual purposes' (LLL II, p. 5.)"
Although
kings and charter assemblies always had specific personal interests which
influenced the content of charter articles, the extent known particular results
could be furthered through charter issue was limited to the point of
negligibility. Limited innovations
could be successfully introduced by arbitrary royal fiat, but not generally by
charter, which were always bound by traditional legal practice.
Hayek's
model of the common law is one of purely private rule creation. The law and the courts are not
creations of the sovereign but rather are evolved institutions within which all
individuals, including the sovereign, must operate. Common law antedates legislation, drawing on preexisting
implicit societal rules or customs, as well as on previous judicial decisions
(LLL I, p. 72). "It is by
deference to this preexisting opinion that the common law judge can lay claim
to authority and legitimacy." (Rizzo, 1985, pp. 868-869.)
Charters
made preexisting implicit societal rules and opinion explicit, but also
emphasized some principles at the expense of others. Like any judicial decision, charter articles took existing
legal principles and adapted them to specific instances. Because they were selective, they
promoted the growth of influence of certain principles and the obsolescence of
others, thus contributing to the evolution of the common-law tradition, again,
just like any legal decision.
3. The Constitutions of Clarendon
The
Constitutions make very clear they are not asserting new legislation. The preamble states "…this
memorandum or inquest was made of some part of the customs and liberties and
dignities of his predecessors, viz., of king Henry his grandfather and others,
which ought to be observed and kept in the kingdom." Henry I had been succeeded by Stephen,
and royal authority had withered in the civil war and unrest that culminated in
Henry II's accession.
"On
account of the dissensions and discords which had arisen between the clergy and
the Justices of the lord king, and the barons of the kingdom concerning the
customs and dignities, this inquest was made in the presence of the archbishops
and bishops, and clergy and counts, and barons and chiefs of the kingdom. And
these customs, recognized by the archbishops and bishops and counts and barons
and by the nobler ones and elders of the kingdom, Thomas Archbishop of
Canterbury, and Roger archbishop of York, and Gilbert bishop of London, [eleven
more bishops are listed,] did grant; and, upon the Word of Truth did orally
firmly promise to keep and observe, under the lord king and under his heirs, in
good faith and without evil wile,-in the presence of the following:
[thirty-seven lay nobles are listed by name,] and many other chiefs and nobles
of the kingdom, clergy as well as laity."
It is
clear from the preamble that the charter assembly participated as witnesses and
guarantors. But the Constitutions
are at least putatively the testimony of the assembly regarding the content
of England's ancient laws and
customs.
3.1
Historical Context
On the death of William the Conqueror in
1087, the English throne and the French dukedoms of Normandie and Maine should
have gone to the oldest son Robert, but William provided his second son,
William II, a letter to the Archbishop of Canterbury indicating his desire that
the younger William be crowned king of England. William I left the French dukedoms to the oldest son Robert
in his will. The kingdom was kept
intact when Robert sold Normandie and Maine to William II for 10,000 marks,
using the money to participate in the Crusades.
William
II died in 1100 without children and was succeeded by the next younger brother
Henry I, though again Robert should have inherited the throne. The extreme irregularity of the
succession after the conquest prompted Henry I's famous coronation
charter. Because many abuses were
complained of during Norman rule since the conquest, Henry I promised to
observe many specific laws and customs relating to the administration,
disposal, and revenues of church lands, and relating to inheritance of property
by nobles. He also promised to
restore the laws and customs to the time of Edward the Confessor, the
next-to-last Saxon king, who died in 1066.
Henry I used the charter to help gain
the consent of the governed to his legally questionable, though formally
uncontested, possession of the throne.
The charter was transmitted to the sheriff of each county, and kept in
an abbey or some suitable location, though in the reign of John (1199-1216), a
copy the nobles desired for reference could only be found with great
difficulty. Henry I never gave his
charter further thought. Its
articles would have no significance if they had not become embodied in later
more validly executed charters, including the Constitutions of Clarendon and
Magna Charta.
Henry I died in 1135 and was succeeded,
again irregularly, by his nephew Stephen.
His one surviving daughter, Matilda, had married the Holy Roman Emperor
Henry V, then the Count of Anjou, Geoffrey Plantagenet. Stephen reigned nineteen unhappy years
marked by civil war and widespread breakdown of law and order in England and
the French territories. Stephen
was captured and Matilda crowned in 1141, but the civil war continued until a
general settlement was made in 1153, in which Stephen was allowed to remain on
the throne, but would be succeeded by the son of Matilda and Geoffrey, Henry
II, in 1154.
One of
Henry's aides, Thomas Becket, studied civil and canon law at the University of
Bologna (Hume I, p. 306), and after serving as chancellor, became Archbishop of
Canterbury in 1162. As Archbishop,
Becket was as rigorous in defending Church prerogatives as he had been zealous
in defending royal privileges as chancellor. Becket attempted to evict certain of the king's
tenants-in-chief claiming the tenures were on church lands. To enforce these claims, Becket issued
writs summoning the tenants to his canon law court, where Becket would be both
judge and plaintiff. The two
nobles were summarily excommunicated for non-appearance, though the judgements
were eventually vacated at the king's command.
Next, a clergyman was accused of rape
and murder in Worcestershire. Becket
confined the suspect in his own prison, preventing seizure by the civil
authorities, and insisted the most severe punishment that could be legally
imposed was degradation from holy orders.
The king insisted on a criminal trial in the temporal courts once the
suspect had been degraded, but Becket claimed a civil trial would violate the
prohibition against double jeopardy.
Henry
II convened the assembly that drafted the Constitutions in a period of
temporary reconciliation with Becket.
Henry required ecclesiastical courts revert to their original sphere of
jurisdiction before the unrest and wished to restore the practices of his
grandfather Henry I. Beckett felt
duty-bound to oppose the king, but eventually was either browbeat into
submission, or recognized further conflict with the king did not serve the
Church's ends.
3.2 The Sixteen Articles
The
Constitutions of Clarendon are a charter of the separation of church and
state. It is especially
interesting to see such a document arise out of the age of faith. Each article reins in the growing power
of the Church, either removing rights and immunities acquired during the reign
of Stephen by the clergy as a special class, or limiting the range of
jurisdiction of canon law courts to what it had been before Stephen's reign.
Article
1 gave the civil courts exclusive jurisdiction over issues of advowson and
presentment. Advowson was the right to present a candidate for installation to
a vacant church office. Kings had
the right to name bishops. Suits
involving these rights, which could only be claimed by lay nobles, had to be
determined in civil courts, though prior to the Constitutions, they were often
settled in canon law courts. The
civil courts would determine these issues and the Church would be subject to
the civil courts in these issues. Advowson
was a jealously guarded privilege in the middle ages. Hume (I, p. 495) relates a particularly barbaric penalty
imposed by Henry II's father Geoffrey of Anjou to assert his right of
advowson. In Magna Charta (1215),
John (1199-1216) was forced renounce this privilege. As the Great Charter was reissued by successive kings,
advowson was eventually abandoned.
Article 2 preserved the king's property rights in churches on his
personal lands.
Article
3 eliminated benefit of clergy and provided clergymen accused of criminal
offenses would be tried in civil court.
Because Pope Alexander III abrogated the Constitutions, this article did
not remain in effect. It was
claimed there were more than one hundred unpunished cases of murder committed
by clergymen in the ten years before the Constitutions. This article attempted to correct a
major shortcoming of criminal law, and specified a regular form of due process
for criminal cases where the accused was a clergyman. The detailed specification of formal process was positive
legislation, but Article 3's clear intent is to provide a uniform procedure to
implement existing common law.
Until
benefit of clergy was formally abolished by statute in 1826 (7 and 8 George IV,
c. 28, s. 6), convicted felons could escape capital punishment in the United
Kingdom if they could recite the opening lines of Psalm 51. On conviction for the second capital
offense, felons could be executed, because double jeopardy was not involved on
conviction for a second offense. Because
of the English common-law tradition, benefit of clergy had to be abolished in
the United States by statute in 1790 (Act of April 30 1790, s. 30).
The murder of a clergyman by a layperson
was not punishable except by excommunication and could be atoned for by penance
and submission. It is interesting
to note that article 3 also provides for a right of supervision of the
ecclesiastical courts by officers to be appointed by the king's justices.
Article 4 forbade subjects from leaving
the kingdom without the king's permission. Article 5 provided that excommunicated persons would be
allowed to remain in their place of abode without having to pay pledges,
preventing the Church from profiting from excommunication.
Article
6 provided a lay person could not be accused before a Church court without
reliable and legal accusers, who must be sworn by the civil authority, the
sheriff. This removed arbitrary
power of the bishops by limiting their jurisdiction over lay people and
providing lay people with procedural rights by imposing a uniform
procedure. The civil
authorities were required to assist the ecclesiastical authorities on
request. As with Article 3,
Article 6 constitutes positive legislation in that it specifies a detailed
uniform procedure, but only to implement existing common law.
Article 7 provided that the king's chief
nobles could not be excommunicated until and unless the king received an
opportunity to judge the offending noble.
In effect, no chief noble could be excommunicated without the king's
consent. Only a feudal lord or the
king could come under an interdict.
Excommunication could apply to anyone, cutting them off from the Church,
but interdiction was a proscription against rendering any property due the
offender.
If a feudal
lord was excommunicated, his lands would be placed under an interdict, and
religious services would be minimized.
Mass would be held with only clergy present. Funerals would not be performed, and church bells would not
be rung. If a king were excommunicated,
interdict applied to the whole kingdom.
Article 8 provided there would be no
appeal to the Pope without the king's consent, in ecclesiastical causes. The custom of appealing to Rome had
begun under Henry I whose brother was papal legate for England. The legate was an authority who could
be appealed to, over a decision by the Primate-Archbishop, or any inferior
Church authority. Appeals to the
Pope seem to have started because of the legate's obvious conflict-of-interest,
and once the precedent was established, the practice continued after the death
of Henry I. The fragmented reign
of Stephen may have allowed certain advantages from appeals beyond the
Archbishop's court.
Article
9 provided civil juries would have the final right of determining which kind of
land tenure is involved in any dispute, and a church court would not have
jurisdiction unless a civil jury first decides the land is church property, or
both parties stipulate the land is church property. About fifteen years after the Constitutions, Ranulph de
Glanville (1187-89?) gives a writ called utrum which shows this practice had
been implemented in spite of extraordinary papal resistance. Again, the specific detailed procedure
is positive, but clearly intended only to implement preexisting common law.
Article 10 provided that certain
protected classes of people could not be excommunicated unless the civil
authority was informed and had an opportunity to compel the accused to appear
in the church court to answer ecclesiastical charges. Summary judgements of excommunication could not be issued
without legal service, and could not be issued for most secular offenses. Secular crimes usually had to be tried
in secular courts, which could not impose excommunication. Prior to the Constitutions, no effort
had ever been made to subject the penalty of excommunication to due process.
Article 11 confirmed the king's right to
receive the medieval pledge of fealty from officers of the church. Article 12 specified a regular
procedure for the election of bishops and other church officials. Article 13 bound the king to compel lay
subjects to respect church property, rights, and revenues. Article 14 forbade the church from detaining
property owed to the king.
Article 15 forbade the Church to enforce
debt payments, reserving this authority to the civil courts. Article 16 provided that the sons of
serfs could not be ordained without the consent of their feudal lord.
Of the
sixteen articles, 5 and 7 deal with excommunication and indirectly provide a
level of due process for this awesome penalty, without actually presuming to
impose internal processes on canon law courts. Where the Constitutions present positive legislation,
describing new and uniform procedures, these are always new procedures
implemented through the civil courts and the secular judicial administration,
including juries, royal justicars, and sheriffs. Articles 1, 2, 9, 11, 13, 14, 15, and 16 limit the Church's
jurisdiction over property rights.
Articles 3, 6, and 10 deal with secular, criminal offenses, removing the
ecclesiastical privilege of benefit of clergy, and limit church jurisdiction
over these offenses. Section 4
confirms the king's supreme temporal authority. Section 8 deals with appeals and section 12 regularizes the
election of bishops and Church officers.
Pope Alexander III abrogated all but six of the least important,
articles 2, 6, 11, 13, 14, and 16.
The
eventual success of the Constitutions is due in part to Henry's persistence in
seeing its articles implemented in the face of opposition from Becket and the
Pope. In spite of archepiscopal
backsliding and equivocation, and papal abrogation, interdict, and anathema,
every term was well enforced, except article 3 removing benefit of clergy -
giving temporal criminal courts the right to try and punish clergy for criminal
offenses. This success in the face
of such overwhelming opposition suggests the Constitutions succeeded because
they served the real secular needs of the state and the people.
3.3 The Role of Positive Legislation
The
innovations of the reign of Stephen required radical changes to correct. Radical change is not typical of the
common-law tradition, but occasionally is required as a correction. Radical change in the form of positive
legislation may be necessitated by the recognition that "past development
was based on error or that it produced some consequences later recognized as
unjust. But the most frequent
cause is probably that the development of the law has lain in the hands of
members of a particular class whose traditional views made them regard as just
what could not meet the more general requirements of justice." (LLL I, p.
89)
Among
the more famous charters issued by Henry II, besides the Constitutions of
Clarendon, are the Assize of Clarendon (1166), the Assize of Northampton
(1176), the Assize of Arms (1176), and the Assize of the Forest (1184), which
also aim at restoring laws and customs of Henry I. The Assizes of Clarendon and Northampton contain notable
positive legislation establishing the jury system. The Assize of Arms revived the Anglo-Saxon militia, a
measure which can be considered simultaneously positive and common-law.
The
medieval clergy possessed particular immunities, rights, and privileges that
made them ill-suited to make impartial judgements over laypeople. Canon and civil law provided the Church
with a variety of special sources of property rights, inheritance, and income,
such as frankalmoin and mortmain tenures.
Although these special privileges needed to be maintained as a part of
the medieval social order, the Church was not the most impartial judge when its
own interests were involved.
Hume
relates that the Church was rigorous in opposing Henry during the conflict with
Becket, but when the king's sons later revolted, Papal bulls and edicts Henry
obtained were not obeyed by the bishops with any zeal, because the Church's
revenues and property rights were not involved. Generally, during the reign of Stephen, ecclesiastical
jurisdiction had only expanded in areas involving Church income and property
and the rights of the clergy. The
Church had not sought to expand its jurisdiction over areas where its interests
were not directly concerned, and where there was no pecuniary incentive.
3.4 The Constitutions and Separation of
Powers
During
the reign of Stephen, church courts, largely out of necessity, extended their
jurisdiction in two fields: 1. they
began to decide civil claims involving church lands, or issues where one party
claimed property belonged to the church, as well as deciding claims involving
the king's and certain nobles' rights of advowson and presentation; and 2. they began to decide criminal cases
against clergymen, and possibly even against laypeople accused of injuring
clergymen. The secular
administration of justice in some counties had become irregular and spotty
during the reign of Stephen.
Because
of the incessant appeal to ancient laws and customs, English charters were not
merely arbitrary royal decrees, though they had at least that much
authority. They possessed an added
moral authority because they tended to minimize positive innovations, and often
repealed unsuccessful legal experiments by returning the realm to an earlier
state of affairs.
Charters
were not parliamentary statutes, as parliament had not yet evolved, but they
were precursors to modern statutes.
The ad hoc assemblies convened to prepare, deliberate, witness, and
guarantee charters were similarly precursors to most modern legislatures. This lineage from the charter
assemblies applies to all Commonwealth parliaments, the U.S. Congress, and to
some extent to all their imitators, and to all U.S. state legislatures. The Icelandic and Norwegian Stortings,
for example, are two legislative bodies which clearly have separate lineages
and independent legal traditions. Nevertheless,
most legislatures with clearly different primary origins must acknowledge the
pervasive influence of the Anglo-American common law tradition.
Charters played an additional
legislative role that seems to have become extinct. Evolving legal practices were often set back several
generations to pre-existing ancient customs. Innovative practices were disowned, but just as often,
common-law practices were confirmed by charter. Modern legislation often arises in response to common law,
with the aim of holding back or undoing judge-made common-law innovations
displeasing to the legislator. It
is not felt necessary to confirm the course of existing common law as it was in
the middle ages.
3.5 Aftermath
The Constitutions introduced no
significant new practices that had not been in place prior to the reign of
Stephen. Most of these practices
had already been restored by Henry II.
Rather than accept the fait accompli, Beckett regretted his
participation almost immediately, and Pope Alexander III ordered Henry to
renounce the Constitutions, under penalty of excommunication and interdict.
After
the abrogation of the Constitutions, the king prosecuted the Archbishop in an
extraordinary and arbitrary manner, first charging him with wrongful possession
of certain manors. When Becket
sent four knights to answer these civil charges, and to apologize for his
inability to appear in person due to illness, the king had him charged with
contempt and non-appearance. This
was indeed harsh justice, and extremely manipulative on the king's part. Henry seems to have taken his cue from
Becket's own earlier summary excommunication of two nobles for nonappearance.
When
Becket appeared in person, the king required an immediate accounting of all
ecclesiastical revenues Becket had administered while chancellor. Hume points out (I, p. 319) that if
Henry had not been extremely pleased with Becket's performance as chancellor,
he would never have made him Archbishop.
Appeals
to the Pope in ecclesiastical causes were made illegal by the Constitutions of
Clarendon, but appeals in civil cases were unheard of, although clearly the
king was exercising arbitrary power over Becket, not justice. "In 1174, after Becket's
murder, Henry was obliged to expressly permit appeals to Rome. Papal influence was to increase in
England until it reached its zenith under Innocent III, liege lord and
collector of tribute." (Henderson 1896)
It seems possible Henry might have
succeeded in promulgating the Constitutions if he had adopted an incremental
approach. One charter might have
first restored civil property and inheritance rights, and the right of advowson
and presentment, and a separate charter reasserted authority of criminal courts
to try clergymen accused of criminal charges. Nevertheless, virtually all articles were put into practice
and became customs of the kingdom.
Richard I (1189-1199) was much more arbitrary
in spirit than his father, though perhaps less so than John (1199-1216). When the clergy failed to contribute
their share of a land tax of five shillings on every hyde of land, Richard
decreed the civil courts might not give them any sentence for debts owed to
them, until they paid what they owed to the king. (Hume I, p. 404).
4. Common Law and Problems of
Entrepreneurial Knowledge
The
emergence of a single court system for civil and criminal matters can be
likened to Menger's (1871, pp. 257-271) description of the emergence of money
in a barter economy, but two alternative interpretations can be argued for:
a. artificial - this was an artificial act
engineered by a charismatic king, celebrated in history and literature as
"Supreme Administrator of the Realm" (Hogue 1966, p. 34).
b. natural - this was a spontaneous result
of the English common-law tradition.
The
Constitutions may have been spontaneous, but were not inevitable. Henry's willful, self-interested acts
shape English history. However, he
could not have accomplished what he did outside the context of the common
law. The Constitutions, and
Henry's other legal reforms, provided significant external benefits by
establishing a uniform legal system, just as ecclesiastic encroachment on the
civil and criminal legal authority imposed external costs on all land owners,
and any subject who might be accused of a criminal offense in a canon law
court. In addition, the clergy's
criminal law immunities made it easier for the Church to exploit its advantages
in civil law privilege and land tenures.
When
economic competition is viewed as a resource allocation problem, it assumes a perfect
knowledge never found in reality. The
dynamic competitive process of entrepreneurial discovery is frustrated by
structural distortions of the price vector (Hayek 1949e). Disequilibrium prices provide
misleading information which prevents efficient resource allocation, but also
allows entrepreneurial awareness to exploit market disequilibria, and through
arbitrage, affect adjustment toward equilibrium, the state of perfect
competition (Kirzner 1984a, p. 151).
In removing and limiting the Church's secular legal authority, Henry was
also removing a major structural source of allocative inefficiency in markets
for agricultural land. Disequilibrium
prices offer pure profit opportunities (Kirzner 1984b, p. 160). Some knowledge deficiencies can be
remedied through search, but others can only be remedied by chance, and not
always then. Kirzner (1984b, p.
162) describes this kind of error as "unawareness of one's
ignorance."
Hayek's
(1949b) knowledge problem is the utilization of dispersed knowledge, which no
one person has, and would not and find it worthwhile to acquire and utilize:
"utilization of knowledge which is not given to anyone in its
totality." In addition,
Kirzner recognizes an additional, basic knowledge problem, failure to optimize
with respect to one's true circumstances.
The peculiar circumstance of two parallel legal systems must have
interjected a great deal of uncertainty into decisions relating to land
purchases and capital investment, lowering both expenditures. Conflicting jurisdictions expanded the
sphere for Hayek's knowledge problem to occur, and obscured the true
circumstances agents should have optimized with respect to.
Secure,
well-defined property rights encourage entrepreneurship. Weak, vague, or uncertain property
rights, such as obtain under parallel, conflicting-in-interest legal systems,
complicate the coordination of individual economic agents' plans under either
government planning or catallaxy. Weak
property rights increase the uncertainty of claims to resources, making the
exchange values or relative prices which are based on these claims, less
reliable as guides to action (Ikeda 1998, pp. 43-44).
In
medieval times, Church and secular lands faced segregated markets. Church lands could not be sold, but
could be rented out to provide revenue.
Because Church lands ("frankalmoin" tenures) could not be
transferred or sold, and secular lands ("lay fee") could, the market
value of secular lands should have been higher, all things equal. This price differential should have
resulted from the greater flexibility offered by the fact that lay fees could
be exchanged, and the fact that, as more land was acquired by the Church
through inheritance ("mortmain"), the supply of lay fee land shifted
to the left.
The
rental markets for Church and secular agricultural lands were integrated, and
similar plots should have rented for a price determined by their crop
yield. Because markets for
permanent sale of Church and secular lands were rigidly segregated, the
permanent sales price of secular land must have been depressed below what its
crop yield would have dictated.
In
fact, prior to the Constitutions, the encroachment of canon law on secular
justice also served to depress the value of secular lands by subjecting secular
property rights to greater uncertainty.
Removal of parallel legal systems with competing civil and criminal
jurisdictions lessened the uncertainty and removed suboptimalities which
entrepreneurs systematically exploited to pursue long-run pure profits.
The
direct costs of the church empowering itself to act as both plaintiff and
prosecutor, and to impose criminal penalties on its civil opponents, were
keenly felt by Henry to be unfair, and detrimental to the moral and economic
interests of his realm. He also
must have felt they undermined his personal prestige, power, and finances.
The
Constitutions clearly promoted entrepreneurship by providing an environment
where property rights were more secure.
An additional contribution to entrepreneurial efficiency may be noted:
by removing the distortion to the price vector for agricultural land, removed
some opportunities for riskless arbitrage. Entrepreneurs were redirected toward more productive
activities.
5. Conclusion
Of the
twenty freedoms important to entrepreneurship identified by Harpur (1998, p.
265), the freedoms of entrepreneurial choice, achievement of rewards,
competitive entry and exit, choice of production, choice of marketing,
ownership, choice of ownership form, choice of consumption, and revision, were
strengthened by the civil and criminal procedure articles of the
Constitutions. Freedoms of trade,
markets, and contract were strengthened by the real property articles. Freedoms of work and choice of
occupation, and travel and migration were at least slightly weakened.
The
Constitutions of Clarendon provide a particularly illuminating example of the
emergence of spontaneous social order in the common law. Because the principles embodied in the
Constitutions provided the a foundation for the separation of church and state,
the document remains one of the most important and historically significant of
all medieval charters. This paper
has demonstrated the common-law character and context of the Constitutions, and
of English charters generally, while recognizing their secondary role in
promulgating positive legislation.
The evolution of modern legislatures from the English charter assemblies
was also discussed. The historical
and economic impact of the Constitutions has also been addressed, showing that
the spontaneous evolution of the common law contained in the document also
contributed to the evolution of greater economic efficiency.
Fifty
years after the Constitutions, the Great Charter (1215) purported to be a
restoration of the liberties of the realm in the time of Edward the
Confessor. This had been promised
in the coronation charters of Henry I, Stephen, and Henry II. Archbishop Stephen Langton produced the
Charter of Henry I for assemblies in London and Bury St. Edmonds in 1214.
Magna
Charta, as written, allowed clergy freedom of elections, a right explicitly
removed by the Constitutions. Likewise,
the right to leave the kingdom at will is established. No taxes, in the form of scutage or
aid, can be levied except in three explicit feudal cases: captivity of a
subject's lord, knighting of a lord's eldest son, and marriage of a lord's
eldest daughter, without the consent of the great council of the kingdom. This article is one of the sources of
the House of Commons' and the House of Representatives' privilege of
originating revenue bills.
Like
the Constitutions of Clarendon, the Great Charter was abrogated by the Pope,
this time Innocent III, but subsequently confirmed by Henry III, Edward I,
Edward II, and Edward III. Almost
alone among medieval charters, its grants of rights and privileges to the
common people slowly began to be observed.
The
author thanks Stephen B. Jarrell for much helpful comment and advice. I remain responsible for errors.
References
Edmund
Burke (1792) "Reflections on the Revolution in France," Works,
London: vol. III.
The
Constitutions of Clarendon (1164),
<http://www.yale.edu/lawweb/avalon/medieval/constcla.htm>.
Ranulph
de Glanville, (1187-89?) De Legibus et Consuetudinibus Regni Angliae, On the
Laws and Customs of the English Kingdom, ed. G.E. Woodbine, Yale Historical
Publications, Manuscripts and Texts XIII, New Haven: Yale University Press,
1932.
David
A. Harper (1998) "Institutional Conditions for Entrepreneurship,"
Advances in Austrian Economics, Vol. 5, Stamford, Connecticut: JAI Press, pp.
241-275.
Friedrich
A. Hayek (1960) The Constitution of Liberty, Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
__________
(1973) Law, Legislation and Liberty: Rules and Order (LLL I) Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
__________
(1976) Law, Legislation and Liberty: The Mirage of Social Justice (LLL II)
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Ernest
F. Henderson (1896) Select Historical Documents of the Middle Ages, London:
George Bell and Sons.
David
Hume (1778) History of England, London, new edition, Indianapolis: Liberty
Classics, 1983.
Sanford
Ikeda (1998) "Interventionism and the Progressive Discoordination of the
Mixed Economy," Advances in Austrian Economics, Vol. 5, Stamford,
Connecticut: JAI Press, pp. 37-49.
Israel
M. Kirzner (1973) Competition and Entrepreneurship, Chicago and London,
University of Chicago Press.
__________
(1978) "Economics and Error," Louis M. Spadaro, ed., New Directions
in Austrian Economics, Kansas City, Missouri: Sheed Andrews and McMeel.
__________
(1984a) "Prices, the Communication of Knowledge and the Discovery
Process," The Political Economy of Freedom: Essays in Honor of F.A. Hayek,
K.R. Leube and A.H. Zlabinger, eds., Philosophia Verlag, reprinted in Kirzner,
The Meaning of Market Process, London: Routledge, 1992, pp. 139-151.
__________
(1984b) "Economic Planning and the Knowledge Problem," Cato Journal,
4:2, reprinted in Kirzner, The Meaning of Market Process, London: Routledge,
1992, pp. 152-162.
__________
(1990a) "Knowledge Problems and their Solutions: Some Relevant
Distinctions," Cultural Dynamics, reprinted in Kirzner, The Meaning of
Market Process, London: Routledge, 1992, pp. 163-179.
__________
(1990b) "Discovery, Private Property and the Theory of Justice in
Capitalist Society," Journal des Economistes et des Etudes Humaines, 1:3,
October 1990, pp. 209-224, reprinted in Kirzner, The Meaning of Market Process,
London: Routledge, 1992, pp. 209-226.
Fritz
Kern (1939) Kingship and Law in the Middle Ages, Eng. trans. S.B. Chrimes,
London.
Carl
Friedrich Menger (1871) Principles of Economics, Grundsaetze der
Volkswirtschaftslehre, Eng. trans. James Dingwall and Bert F. Hoselitz, New
York: New York University Press, 1976.
__________
(1883) Investigations into the Method of the Social Sciences with Special
Reference to Economics, Untersuchungen ueber die Methode der
Socialwissenschaften und der Politischen Oekonomie insbesondere, Eng. trans. Francis
J. Nock, New York: New York University Press, 1985.
Montesquieu
(1748) De l'esprit des lois.
Julius
Paulus, Digests, 50.17.1
Francis
Pollock (1890) Oxford Lectures and Other Discourses, London.
Mario
J. Rizzo (1985) "Rules versus Cost-benefit Analysis in the Common
Law," Cato Journal, 4:3, pp. 865-884.
William
I, (c. 1066) "Ordinance of William I Separating the Spiritual and Temporal
Courts," <http://www.yale.edu/lawweb/avalon/medieval/ordwill.htm>.